Kritarchy
The purpose of this note is to provide a short introduction to the political system of
kritarchy and to explain some of the theoretical concepts on which it relies, in
particular natural law and justice.
Kritarchy is the political system based on equal justice for all, which is to say on
respect for natural law. It differs from other political systems by its consistent
adherence to and application of the rules of justice. Even courts of law, police forces
and other organisations that look after the day-to-day business of maintaining law, are
denied any power, privilege or immunity that is not in conformity with natural law. A
kritarchys police forces cannot lawfully use their weapons and coercive powers save
for maintaining law, that is for defending the natural rights of people and remedying
their violation. In contrast with their counterparts in the statist political systems that
prevail in todays world, in a kritarchy courts of law and police forces do not
constitute and are not incorporated into a coercive monopoly. Every person is entitled to
offer judicial or police-services to willing others; no person can be forced to become a
client of any court of law or police force against his will. In short, in a kritarchy
judicial and police-services are offered on a free market, which is the natural law of the
human world in so far as exchanges of goods and services are concerned.
Because of its commitment to equal justice for all, a kritarchy does not know the usual
political distinction between subjects and rulers. It lacks a government in the modern
sense of the word, i.e. an organisation with coercive powers that claims a right to the
obedience or to the use of the labour or the property of those who inhabit or reside in
the area over which its coercive powers are effective. Governing and taxing people by
public or private force are no functions of the political system of kritarchy. People are
to be left free to govern their own affairs, either individually or in voluntary
association with others and this means that in governing his own affairs each is
required to leave others free to govern their own affairs. In this sense, freedom is the
basic law of a kritarchy.
It follows that a kritarchy can only exist in societies where, and as long as, the
commitment to justice is sufficiently strong to defeat the endeavours of those who use
unlawful methods such as aggression, coercion or fraud to further their ends or evade
responsibility and liability for the unlawful wrongs they have caused to others. While it
is theoretically conceivable that freedom can be maintained by no more than unorganised
spontaneous actions of self-defence, in a kritarchy the commitment to justice takes shape
in its political system, which consists of a free market for the organisations of justice
(i.e. courts of law and police forces) and the means for preserving its integrity.
The term kritarchy, compounded from the Greek words kritès
(judge) or krito (to judge) and archè (principle, cause), appears
to be coined in 1844 by the English author Robert Southy. In its construction it resembles
more familiar political terms such as monarchy, oligarchy and hierarchy.
Kritarchy is mentioned in among others Websters Unabridged Dictionary,
The Oxford English Dictionary and the American Collegiate Dictionary. According to its
etymological roots, a kritarchy is a political system in which justice (more exactly the
judgment that seeks to determine justice) is the ruling principle or first cause.
Similarly a monarchy is a system in which one person is supposed to be the ruling
principle or first cause of every legal action, every other person being no more than an
obedient subject of the monarch. In an oligarchy a few persons (the oligarchs), acting in
concert but without a fixed hierarchy among them, are thought to be the source of all
legal actions. In the modern system of parliamentary sovereignty, for example, the members
of parliament constitute an oligarchy. All members have equal standing within the
parliament. However, the results of their deliberations and decisions are supposed to bind
all people who, because of their citizenship or residence, are assumed to be subject to
the authority of the state.
If monarchy denotes rule by one person and oligarchy rule by a
few, it is tempting to understand kritarchy as referring to rule by judges.
However, the use of the word rule should not mislead us into thinking that the
rule of judges is like the rule of monarchs and oligarchs, much less that it is a
particular sort of oligarchy. Monarchs and oligarchs aspire to political rule, i.e. the
ability and power to enforce obedience to their commands, rules, decisions and choices on
their subjects. In short, monarchs and oligarchs rule by a mixture of direct command and
legislation. Judges, on the other hand, are supposed not to legislate but to find ways and
means to settle conflicts and disputes in a lawful manner. They do not seek to enforce
obedience to their commands as such, but respect for law, which is an order of things that
is understood to be objectively given and not something that answers to whatever desires
or ideals the judges may have.
In contrast with other political systems, where they have been incorporated as
magistrates into a system of political rule and empowered to use coercive means to drag
citizens and residents before their benches, judges in a kritarchy have no subjects.
Monarchs and oligarchs impose, or allow their servants (judges, prosecutors) to impose,
their rulings on those of their subjects on which they want to impose them. In other
words, they pick their subjects (which is the root meaning of the Latin
legere, from which the word lex for legislated or statute law is
derived). In a kritarchy on the other hand, judges do not choose which persons will appear
before them. Instead, people desiring to have their conflicts and disputes resolved by
judicial judgment will pick their judge.
The distinctive characteristic of a kritarchy is therefore that it is a political
system without the institution of political rule. If one thinks of it as the rule of
judges, one should remember that these judges enjoy no particular privileges or
special powers. It is the rule of law, not the rule of legislators, judges or
any other category of privileged officials.
There are many historical and even recent examples of kritarchy or near-kritarchy, and
also of attempts to use constitutions and other fundamental charters (such as the Magna
Carta, the Bills of Rights of the Glorious Revolution in the United Kingdom and the
original amendments to the Constitution of the Unites States of America, the French
Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen) to introduce elements of kritarchy as
checks on the powers of states and governments. Unwritten customary laws memorised by
tribesmen, such as to this day the Hherr of the Somalis, the Madha of the Afar and
the Gada of the Oromo, often provide strong support for the decentralisation of power that
is characteristic of kritarchy, even if they derive their authority merely from custom and
not from a conscious and explicit commitment to natural law.
At the end of the second millennium before Christ, the Jews lived in a system described
in the biblical book of the Judges. Their judges were not judges in the
technical sense of the modern legal systems. They were influential respected men who
provided leadership and counsel without having power to coerce or tax. The history of
Celtic and Germanic peoples both before and during their confrontation with Roman
imperialism, is also replete with examples, as is the medieval period after the collapse
of the Roman Empire in the West. Kritarchies were firmly established in medieval Ireland
until it fell victim to British expansionism, in Ireland where it lasted until the middle
of the thirteenth century, and in Frisia where it survived into the sixteenth century. In
the first half of the nineteenth century the European immigrants who settled in the
Mid-West and the Far West in North America developed their own brand of kritarchy. In
Africa and Asia tribal societies have continued to the present day to adhere to some form
of kritarchy, if they have not been submerged in the statist structures imposed by the
colonial powers and the indigenous political rulers who took over in the post-colonial
period.
While these historical realisations or near-realisations of kritarchy may suggest that
it is a primitive political system, it should be borne in mind that most of them fell
victim to conquest or to the firm hold on power established by military lords in times of
war, who turned ostensibly temporary structures for the mobilisation of men and resources
into a permanent apparatus of political rule. It is certainly true that kritarchies are
ill equipped to make or endure war for long periods of time. If that is a serious
weakness, it is also a great virtue. In any case the vulnerability of kritarchies in the
face of massive militarily operations is comparable to that of a small or technologically
backward state confronting the might of a large or technologically advanced neighbour.
Moreover it is problem that we may acknowledge without losing sight of what a kritarchy
has to offer for more normal times.
We began this note with the statement that kritarchy is the political system based on
equal justice for all, that is to say on respect for natural law. What does this mean? The
terms justice and natural law may seem to many to be extremely
vague if not meaningless. Some even consider natural law to be a discredited
notion, an intellectual throwback to a prescientific age. It is alleged that there is no
such thing as natural law or that what is called natural law is nothing more
than an ill-defined set of background principles that may help legislators and judges to
keep their decisions from evoking moral outrage among the public at large. However, in
discussing kritarchy we have to pierce through the veil of confusion that is woven from
these current phantom-notions of natural law. We should therefore take some pains to
explain the precise meaning and operational value of the terms justice and
natural law.
The search for the true origin, nature and function of natural law is an old one. The
first known scholars of human society in the West were the ancient Greeks, who made a
sharp distinction between natural and conventional or artificial law. The so-called
sophists of the fifth century BC came up with the notion of the human world as arising out
of, distinguishing itself from and protecting itself by the progressive perfection of
social and technical skills in a ruthless and dangerous natural environment. They also
made the distinction between the human world and the particular societies that arise from
that world and fall back into it like waves on the surface of the sea. For them the human
world was the world of human history as it appears to one who wants to know how people
cope with the problems of survival and more particularly what people do to one another.
Noting the permanence of the human world and contrasting it with the transient and merely
local significance of particular societies, they began the search for natural law or the
fundamental order of the human world, while debunking the claims of universal, divine or
moral truth made by various political thinkers on behalf of some particular real or
imagined society and its way of life.
Their opponents countered by developing metaphysical theories. With these they
purported to show that true nature cannot be apprehended by the senses or by
experience, but only by complex systems of abstract thought that are beyond the
comprehension of the common run of mankind. The main political thrust of their argument
was that this true nature does indeed vindicate some particular way of life
and/or shape of political organisation. In short, denying that nobody should be presumed
to ignore the law of human relations, they advanced the claim that without the guidance of
experts like themselves, people would never attain anything but a lawless, at best
inferior if not chaotic condition of existence.
These metaphysical theories, in combination with older views on the rule of the gods,
left many people under the impression that natural law has little to do with nature as it
can be observed, but is instead the understanding of what the way of life and the legal
rules of an ideal society or a society under the direct rule of the gods would
have to be. As a result the distinction between the natural universal and permanent order
of the human world and the artificial transient and local orders of particular societies
became blurred as more and more political, ethical and religious claimed the sanction of
natural law. The same happened to the distinction between the rights and duties that have
their ground in the natural conditions of human interaction and those that happen to be
granted or imposed by rulers seeking to mobilise their subjects according to their own
religious or ideological inclinations.
Nevertheless, even within the general framework of metaphysical and theological
speculation the attempts to discover and elucidate those distinctions were not abandoned.
In his De Vita Spirituali Animae of 1402, Jean de Gerson, a theologian and rector at the
Sorbonne University in Paris, laid the foundations for the development of a category of
human rights that even God would have to respect. In the turbulent period of the religious
wars in Europe that was soon to follow, the concept of natural rights became a prominent
weapon in the intellectual arsenal of persecuted minorities and later of a more general
resistance to the claims of absolutist rulers and the ambitions of power-grabbing
politicians. It is little wonder that natural law and natural rights became significant
influences on the process of constitution making in the western states of the eighteenth
and nineteenth century. As a result freedom and property were, at least for a time, given
a degree of legal protection that is rare in the history of political rule.
At the same time the advances of economic and sociological science tended to promote
the general acceptance of the philosophy of natural law. Is was understood that within the
constraints of natural law that is to say in societies in which freedom and
property are relatively safe from private and public aggression the desire for
wealth and personal betterment leads men onto the road of material progress.
Unfortunately, towards the end of the nineteenth century this understanding gradually gave
way to the notion that material progress (progressive evolution) is the
natural law of the human world. Consequently, wealth and welfare were taken to
be the true natural rights of men, and justice was re-interpreted
to mean the efficient production and fair distribution of wealth. Economic and
social policies, and the theories that inspired them, began to wear down the constraints
of natural law that had not long before been accepted in constitutions and legislative
enactments. Despite this setback more or less original work in the field of natural law
continues to be done, some of it such as the works of Ayn Rand and Murray Rothbard
reaching large audiences worldwide. Other significant work received much less
attention, for example Frank van Duns book on the fundamental principle of law (1982
in Dutch), which makes a clear distinction between the question What is natural
law? and the question Why should people respect natural law? and
provides rigorously argued answers to both. Nevertheless, for the great majority of
intellectuals natural law is still little more than prescientific metaphysical
speculation, while some of those who would otherwise have been sympathetic to it, have now
subscribed to the belief that economic analysis and efficient policy have superseded the
science of law and the quest for justice as the main safeguards of order in the human
world.
In order to clarify the notion of natural law, we have first of all to dispel the
common idea that in natural law the word law stands for a command,
rule, norm or other directive statement, or that it states an exception to such a
directive. According to that interpretation a law commands, forbids or permits as
if the meaning of a law is that something ought or should be done or omitted,
or that doing or omitting it is left to the discretion of those to whom the law is
addressed. In short, law is used here as the translation of the Latin word
lex, the original meaning of which was connected to the mobilisation of armies
and the organisation of military campaigns, and which later came to denote any general
rule or command issued by the highest political authorities.
What is wrong with this interpretation? First of all, it is no more than a historical
accident that the word law came to be used as the translation of
lex. It was also and more properly used to translate the Latin
ius, which has nothing to do with the exercise of political authority.
Ius denotes a bond or obligation arising out of a personal commitment made in
solemn speech (iurare, to swear) and in a more general sense the order of
human affairs that arises out of such mutual commitments. In other words, ius
presupposes a condition in which people meet as free and equal persons and arrange their
affairs by mutual agreements, contracts or covenants. This is in clear contrast to
lex, which presupposes that one man can unilaterally oblige another.
From this etymological perspective it is no wonder that those who have tried interpret
natural law as lex naturalis, have been led to formulate complicated
metaphysical and theological theories to explain how nature can be a legislator or how one
can separate from the various directive forces of nature (urges, inclinations,
desires and the like) those that deserve to be included in the list of natural
laws and those that do not (and therefore have to be considered
unnatural or against nature). None of these theories have been
able to convince even sympathetic sceptics. Without the hypothesis of a divine legislator,
who for some unfathomable reason prefers to encrypt his commands in nature, theories of
leges naturales get nowhere and with that hypothesis, non-believers can
only conclude that they are conjured up out of thin air.
There may in the end be only one very thin excuse for using the term natural
law in the sense of lex naturalis: just like the leges of a political
authority, which bind or oblige people without their consent, the natural laws are
supposed to oblige everyone regardless of anyones consent. However, that analogy
gives us no clue as to how we can determine the directive content of any natural law. It
merely identifies it as an unspecified something that is like a lex in that it
has the power to oblige without consent, but also unlike a lex it that it is
not backed up by the power to enforce.
Unlike the French loi or the Italian legge the English word
law does not derive from lex. Its etymological root is the
Germanic laeg, which denotes order, while its opposite orlaeg
denotes the dissolution of order, confusion and in particular a condition of war.
Law in this sense refers to peace, freedom and friendly relations the
absence of warlike actions that turn people into enemies and threaten their freedom by
exposing them to the risk of injury, death, slavery or loss of property. The Latin word
for warlike action is iniuria, that is to say an action that is not in
conformity with ius. Thus, ius and law seem to be conceptually
(though not etymologically) related. Both refer to a condition of order in human affairs
that is characterised by the absence of warlike interaction. It should immediately be
clear that law in this sense does not suggest a directive content. Law is not
a command, rule or norm, nor is it a collection or system of such directive elements. It
is an objective condition that many people may and in fact do value. As such it may
inspire them to formulate rules of conduct that help to bring it about or to restore it
when it is impaired. We may call such rules rules of law, but we should then
always remember that they are only related to law as means to an end and that they
deserve to be called rules of law only because they have the establishment or restoration
of law (or ius) as their end. For that reason they may also be called rules of justice,
because the literal meaning of justice (Latin: iustitia) is what is
conducive to ius. In other words, justice is what aims at the establishment of the
condition in which people interact on the basis of mutual consent. Justice is respect for
law in the sense of ius. Justice does not imply respect for the laws (leges)
that might be enforced by the authorities, except in those cases when they are genuine
rules of law.
If law means order and not command, rule or norm, natural law
is no longer a mystifying concept. It stands for the natural order of the human world. It
is in this sense that the term natural law enters into the definition of
kritarchy. The question before us is: What is the natural law or order of the human world?
Order in the human world certainly implies that there is no confusion among persons.
This is the case when words, works and actions can be traced to their true authors and
when their consequences to the extent that these objectively or materially affect
others are either borne by the authors themselves or else by willing or consenting
others. When human affairs are in order, no person need fear that others realise their
projects, or take credit for his words, actions or works at his expense but without his
agreement. No one can successfully hide his own responsibility for what he said, did or
brought about. There is then no confusion as to who is innocent or guilty of a crime, who
owes a debt to whom, who was and who was not a participant in some particular undertaking
or practice, who participated voluntarily and who was forced or tricked to participate,
which exchanges were concluded by mutual consent and which were not, and so on.
Order or law in the human world is that condition in which each person is free from the
threat of injurious actions from others, able to live his life and to enjoy his property
in an environment of peaceful, friendly relations. To each his own is
therefore the defining characteristic of law. To maintain that order requires respect for
it, i.e. justice, as the guiding principle of human action. That respect includes the
constant will to leave or if necessary to return to each his own that is to say the
will to avoid causing physical damage to the person, work or property of any other, to
honour lawful contracts and to provide full restitution or compensation to those to whom
one has nevertheless caused unlawful harm, as well as the will not to hinder those who
seek lawful remedies for unlawful wrongs done to themselves or others.
The foregoing certainly defines a coherent notion of order or law in the human world
but is it the natural order, the natural law of the human world? In order to answer
that question we have to take a closer look at the human world. It is first of all a world
constituted by the existence of many different and separate yet similar natural persons
who are alike in their freedom, i.e. their capacity for independent action, speech and
thought and for communicating their thoughts, intentions and expectations to one another
in a rational way. In almost all cases humans are by nature physically separate and in
many respects different beings, and in those extremely rare cases when they are not
physically separate as with Siamese twins they are nevertheless
distinguishable persons who can separately take credit or be held to account for what they
say or do because they too are individually free agents.
Now the concept of law, as it was described above, qualifies as a concept of natural
law if and to the extent that the distinctions that constitute it are objective facts of
nature. That is without doubt the case. Human beings are naturally distinct, indeed
separate beings. Therefore, it is certainly possible in principle to identify the true
author(s) of any particular words, works or actions, however difficult the attempt may
prove to be in actual situations. There is in principle an objectively true answer to
questions about the authorship of anything done or said by human beings, and therefore
also about the extent of any persons lawful property that is to say, as we
shall see shortly, the extent of his right. Questions as to what is mine and what is
thine, can be answered with reference to objective facts. But then there is also in
principle an objectively true answer to the question whether one persons sayings or
doings do or do not cause unlawful harm to another by invading or infringing upon the
latters right.
In order to avoid misunderstanding, we should note that not all objective or even
natural distinctions enter into the definition of natural law. Age, gender, length and
weight of body, colour of skin or hair, proficiency in mathematics or any number of other
properties or characteristics that are or conceivably might be 'given by nature',
are not taken into account. They are properties or characteristics of individual persons,
but their presence or absence to a greater or smaller degree in any individual does not
determine the answer to the question whether that individual is a person or not. In their
multifarious combinations they account for a great many differences among persons, but
that is all they do. No matter how different persons are in any dimension of shape or
talent, they are all persons because of their innate or genetically given freedom of
action, speech, thought and rational communication. In that crucial respect they are all
alike.
Freedom is indeed the reality of a person, his very being. It is physically impossible
to take away a persons real freedom without at the same time destroying him as a
person (by killing him or driving him insane). Now it is certainly true that the
destruction of a persons real freedom can come about as the result of many causes,
but not all of these are relevant from the perspective of natural law. It is only when
such causes originate within the human world, i.e. from the actions of another person,
that the question of the lawful or unlawful character of the destruction of a
persons real freedom arises. This is so because natural law is the order of the
human world as such, constituted by the existence of many different and separate human
beings.
If there is no way to separate a person from his real freedom without destroying both
at the same time, it is possible and unfortunately easy enough to destroy a
persons opportunities for exercising his personal capacities without destroying him.
We need to distinguish between a persons real freedom and his organic freedom, the
latter being his activity or work as a person. It is again undeniable that any number of
circumstances and accidents can cause a temporary or definitive destruction or limitation
of a persons organic freedom, but again and for the same reason that we noted
before, it is only when such causes originate within the human world that the question of
their lawful or unlawful character arises.
Once the notion of natural law is properly understood as the order of the natural world
of free persons, it is easy to grasp the concept of natural right. The word
right can be used in two different but related senses: the one captures the
static aspect of a right, the other its dynamic aspect. In the static sense a
persons natural right is the place or space he occupies lawfully in the natural
order of the human world it is his property. That space is first of all determined
by his physical being as a person, and is therefore immediately filled by his real
freedom.
Because a natural persons presence is marked not just by his simply being
there but also by his activity and work which in almost all circumstances is
the condition of his existence and survival his work is also constitutive of his
place in the human world and therefore of his natural right. Here we meet the dynamic
aspect of a right. An obvious qualification must be noted here, because as we have seen
already a persons work or actions can interfere with and even destroy anothers
organic freedom and thereby step outside the order or law of the human world. It is
therefore only by his lawful activity, that is in so far as he respects the rights of
others, that a person can add to his natural right. In the dynamic sense a right denotes
any personal action or pattern of behaviour that is in accordance with natural law. Just
as natural right in the static sense denotes space lawfully occupied by a
persons being and work in the natural order of the human world, just so
natural right in the dynamic sense denotes lawful activity, i.e. activity that
is respectful of that order. Natural law and natural rights are two sides of the same
coin.
Thus, a persons natural right denotes the space of real and organic freedom that
coincides with his being and his work. It is therefore as objectively ascertainable as
they are. The distinctions that constitute the natural law being facts of nature, natural
law is an objective category and so are natural rights.
Answering questions such as What is natural law? and What facts are
to be taken into account in discovering the extent of a persons rights? does
not by itself provide an answer to the question why we should respect natural law or the
natural rights of others. Why should we respect others as the free persons they
undoubtedly are (except perhaps to metaphysicians who invoke their own elaborate
abstractions to deny the separateness of persons or even their existence as agents)? In
what way can natural law be obligatory if it is not some rule backed by force
or powerful opinion but an objectively identifiable condition of the human world? In what
way can the fact that one has no right to do something be a compelling reason for not
doing it even if one has the power to do it, wants to do it and stands to profit from
doing it? And why should the fact that one has a right to do something constitute a
compelling reason for others not to interfere unlawfully with his doing it, even if they
can and want to interfere and expect to be better off as a result of their interference?
There are usually many prudential arguments in support of a positive answer to such
questions but often also many prudential arguments in support of a negative answer.
Even in well-ordered societies crime does pay occasionally! Taken together, such arguments
can lead to no better conclusion than that a person should respect natural law when in his
estimation the arguments for doing so outweigh those for not doing so, but not when the
balance tilts the other way. No absolute obligation can emerge from such deliberations.
That is not surprising because their purpose is not to answer the question whether we
should respect natural law, but only the question whether in the particular circumstances
of the case we can profit more by doing one thing rather than another.
In their wish to ascribe absolute and unconditional obligatory force to natural law,
many have been tempted to place its source outside the human world itself, for example in
some metaphysical, divine or supernatural domain. Unfortunately, for most people, that
move merely obscures the issues, if it does not completely mystify them. Fortunately,
however, such a move is also unnecessary. The question as to whether we should respect the
natural order of the human world is not the same as whether it is at all times in every
persons interests to do so, no matter what his interests might be. It is a question
that arises only in human in the context of human interaction, where one person faces
another, and not in the context of solitary deliberation.
In the face-to-face context, the question is whether each of us should respect the
rights of the other. It turns out that he who would attempt to argue that he should not
respect the others natural rights, inevitably involves himself in dialectical
contradiction by denying the very conditions he is presupposing in presenting his argument
as something to be taken seriously by his opponent as well as by himself. It would be as
if he was saying: I am taking you seriously and I expect you to take me seriously,
therefore I expect you to take me seriously when I say seriously that I should not take
you seriously. In short, he would be saying: I respect you, therefore I shouldnt
which is absurd.
There is in fact no way in which the proposition that we you and I should
respect each other, can be defeated in any rational argument between us. But the order or
law of the human world is precisely that condition in which people are prepared to enter
into rational argument, each taking the other seriously, and to carry out the commitments
they undertake in so talking to one another. This is exactly what the word ius
conveys. Consequently, if we take ourselves seriously, the conclusion that we are under
the obligation to respect one another, is inescapable. This fundamental obligation entails
that each is bound to respect others as long as they respect him, and that each has a
right to the respect of others as long as he respects them.
These are not empty formulas. The persons they refer to are real beings. By applying
the fundamental obligation to the facts of the human world, especially the separateness
and distinctiveness of persons, we can derive the natural rights (and corresponding
duties) of human beings, progressively extending the argument by taking seriously the
rights derived in its previous steps. With respect to the more basic dynamic natural
rights, the argument might proceed according to the following pattern.
Because their innate or genetically given capacity for independent action, speech and
thought is the determining factor of their particularly human mode of existence, human
beings can and indeed must think, speak and act. The natural right to do these things
cannot be rationally denied in a lawful manner. That is so because any denial that
pretends to be rational would involve thinking, speaking and acting and would therefore
assert its own unlawfulness. Only by refusing to think and speak (even to oneself), by
behaving without thought can one deny these natural rights, but then that
denial has no rational aspect whatsoever and places the denier outside the order of the
human world. Thinking implies judging and making choices, accepting one idea, opinion,
plan or valuation, or rejecting it for another, while remaining conscious of the
alternatives that were rejected. Every action carries with it the long shadow of what was
not but could have been done instead. Thus, human beings can and must choose. Making
choices is an inevitable and therefore necessary condition of man. Choosing not to choose
is still to make a choice, and to wander through life without making choices, with no
consciousness of any might-have-been, is not possible for any human being who is not
raised to be a mute pet in the care of others. Being human implies the right to think,
speak, judge, make choices and act. To deny these rights to any human person is to deny
his very being. But such a denial logically entails that the denier renounces his own
rights and makes himself an outlaw.
Taking the static and the dynamic aspects together, we see that a persons natural
right is that part of the world a person he can point to while saying truthfully
That is my right, and that it is also some activity about which he can say
truthfully That is what I have a right to do. John Lockes famous formula
Life, liberty and property is a useful summation of natural rights. Life and
property exemplify the static aspect of a persons natural right, while liberty (that
is organic freedom constrained by the natural order of the human world) exemplifies its
dynamic aspect.
From the perspective of natural law a person is entitled to say that his life, liberty
and property are his right. It does not make sense for him to say that he has a right to
any life, liberty or property but his own. Natural rights are therefore not to be confused
with the so-called human rights of the United Nations Universal
Declaration of Human Rights of 1948. On the basis of that Declaration I can say that I
have rights to life, liberty and property, but not to my life, liberty or property. That
is so because in order to guarantee others their human rights the political
authorities must be able to arrange my and everybody elses life, liberty and
property according to their own estimation of what is feasible and appropriate in
accordance with the organisation and resources of each state. The operational
essence of the doctrine is that my human right gives the state a legal ground
for taxing you and subsidising me, while your human right gives it a legal
ground for doing the opposite. Both rights together provide it with a legal ground for
taxing and subsidising as it sees fit.
From a philosophical perspective the human rights of the Declaration are
all variations on the Hobbesian theme that human beings have an enforceable
right to have their needs and desires satisfied at the expense of the life,
liberty and property of others a right that can have no place in
natural law because its enforcement would entail massive violations of natural rights. The
perversion of the notion of natural law that was introduced in the mid-seventeenth century
by the famous apostle of the absolute state, Thomas Hobbes, had as its starting point the
idea that men have a natural right to anything they desire, even if getting it involves
killing or enslaving others. In short, every mans natural right is to rule the world
(if he can) or, equivalently, injustice is mans natural right (if he can get
away with it). Noting that only chaos can follow if every person were to act according to
that right not to respect others, Hobbes did not retrace his steps to check
the absurd premise of his argument. Instead he went on to argue that the only way out of
the unorganised injustice that is mans natural condition, is to organise
(i.e. monopolise) injustice in the form of the state. Thus Hobbes founded the
characteristic philosophy of the modern state, that the basic human right is satisfaction
of desire and that the main business of the state is to use political power to determine
whose desires shall be satisfied to what extent and at whose expense. Note however that in
his system justice is nothing more than the consequence of the organisation of
a legal monopoly of coercion designed to enforce obedience to the legal directives of the
powers that be. Law, right and justice, in the proper understanding of these terms, have
no place in that system, yet it is the basis of the ruling political ideology in the West,
of its doctrine of human rights no less than of its reverence for the
political system of democracy.
It may well be true that democracy is the worst of all systems of political rule except
for all the others, but it is nevertheless a system in which some presume to have the
right to govern the rest regardless of their consent. As such it is still unacceptable
from the point of view of natural law as well as incompatible with the political system of
kritarchy. The fundamental defect of democracy is not that people vote to determine which
individuals shall be their political representatives. The central defect and in fact
irreparable defect of democracy is that it embodies the right of the
representatives to rule over those who voted for them as well as over those who did not.
It allows the elected rulers to violate the natural rights of people with impunity, at
least if they do so in a proper legal way by specifying in advance and in sufficient
detail how it should be done, by which magistrates or officers of the state, where people
can complain if they feel their rights are improperly violated, and so on. As in other
systems of political rule, there is in a democracy no independent police or judiciary to
which people can appeal. A democracy outlaws all independent sources of protection of
natural rights as a matter of constitutional necessity, in order to make sure that no
natural rights can be invoked against the legal rights of democratic rule.
Democracy is often presented as government by consent, but that is never
more than the consent of a majority and in many democracies not even that. As a
political device democracy is no doubt a great invention. Regular elections provide a
rough mechanism for ensuring an alignment of rulers and a sizeable part of the subjects
over which they rule. They thereby help to prevent or minimise the violent confrontations
and unrelenting repression and exploitation that are permanent risks in other systems of
rule. Nevertheless, they are a practice that has no basis in natural law. To understand
this, it suffices to ask how a person could lawfully authorise another to do what he
himself has no right to do. The question is pertinent, because, to repeat, democracy is a
system of political rule in which there is a distinction between the rulers and the rules,
and between the legal rights of the rulers and those of the ruled. If you would attempt to
do to your neighbours what a democratic government does to its citizens say tax
them, fix their hours of work, force them to accept the money you have printed or to send
their children to schools of your choice , you would very likely (and in any case
should) end up in jail. Not even a democracy allows you to do such things. Nor does it
allow you to do them in conspiracy with others. But it does allow you to have someone else
do them on your behalf and in your name! All you have to do is vote for a political
representative.
The mystery of democracy is that representatives are invested with powers
the people who empowered them are not (and should not be) allowed to exercise. Of course,
the mystery is only apparent. It disappears as soon as we recall the Hobbesian foundation
of democracy: there is nothing wrong with injustice as long as it is properly monopolised,
and democracy is an appropriate means for doing so. More fundamentally, in a democracy
every voter is assumed to have the right to decide who should control the coercive
monopoly and rule everybody else in the state. That is obvious in the admittedly unlikely
case that you are the only voter to turn up at the polls. Then your vote decides which
party should take over parliament and the government as if you were an absolute
ruler picking his counsellors and ministers.
Leaving no room for the idea that human beings are natural persons in a natural world,
the current legal and political ideology makes any man or woman an artificial being
a citizen whose very essence is defined and created by the legal rules
of the state to which he or she belongs. Within the state human beings as such have no
rights, except in so far as some legal authority regulates their existence and freedom.
That is why the Universal Declaration in its articles 6 and 15 names a legal
personality and a nationality among the things people have a right to.
From the point of view of the Declarations underlying philosophy, a legal
personality and a nationality in a word citizenship must be
eminently desirable, for they are nothing less than the necessary conditions of legal
existence in the state. Without them a person is a nobody. Once we abandon the perspective
of natural law for that of legal rule, we must admit that what a person has a right to do
or to call his own, depends not on what he is or does, but on his status in the legal
order in which he happens to find himself. He becomes an artificial person in an
artificial order, like a piece of wood that is assigned different rights and
duties depending on whether it is used in a game of chess, checkers or backgammon.
The glorification of such artificial legal orders is very common in contemporary legal
and political thought, where fiction seems to triumph invariably over reality. Artificial
orders are based on artificial or imaginary distinctions and on the neglect of or
disregard for natural distinctions. Thus we may think of orders that arbitrarily or
systematically refuse to acknowledge certain persons as persons. Other examples of
artificial law proceed by defining some or all persons as being in all or some respects
part of others, to which they are therefore said to belong. Some go so far as
to define human beings as parts of non-existent imaginary or fictitious persons. In fact,
however, natural persons are not parts of other natural persons or legal
fictions. They may become members in some association or society, and in that sense become
participants in its activities, but that does not imply that they are thereby
mysteriously transformed in mere parts of a person and it does not
imply that the association is a person in its own right.
No matter what the philosophical pretensions behind the constructions of artificial law
may be, they all share a common practical implication. They deny the freedom and/or the
equality of at least some human persons, and thereby provide a spurious justification for
the claim that from the perspective of law some human persons either do not exist at all
or exist only in so far as they are represented by others. Thus, by denying
natural law and the natural distinctions that constitute it, they conjure up an idea of
law that makes the non-consensual government of one person by another seem
lawful.
It should be sufficiently clear by now that natural law is not a question
of idle speculation, but of natural fact. In this sense a kritarchy is a political system
based on respects for the facts (though not necessarily for the artefacts) of the human
world. Respect for natural law is therefore an objective category of human action. Human
actions that respect law are lawful and therefore just. Those that do not, are unlawful
and unjust.
Justice in the general sense is the art or skill of acting in conformity with law, with
due regard for the rights of other persons. In the particular technical sense
it is the art or skill of discovering rules, methods and procedures that effectively and
efficiently provide for the defence and, if need be, fortification and restoration of the
law of the human world. The discovery, refinement and systematisation of such rules,
methods and procedures are the proper province of jurisprudence as a rational discipline.
In an evolved kritarchy jurisprudence is the business of specialists, jurists, who
supply their skills in an open market to individuals and organisations, but also and
perhaps primarily to courts of law, police forces and other organisations that are
involved in enforcing respect for natural law and helping people to make their actions
conform to the requirements of justice. As noted before, in a kritarchy neither the courts
of law nor the police forces nor any of the other organisations that make justice their
business, have any legal monopoly. Their clientele and membership remain free to shift
their demand from an unsatisfactory to a hopefully more satisfactory supplier of justice.
Consequently, courts of law and police forces have a strong economic incentive to avoid
using violence or other coercive means, say to compel a person to appear in court, unless
they have good reason to believe that he is guilty as charged or is obstructing the course
of justice and sufficient insurance to cover their liabilities.
Not being above the law, the courts and police forces of a kritarchy run the risk of
being charged with unlawful behaviour in another court, if they deprive others of their
freedom or other rights when justice does not require it. That other court might be a
competitor or a cooperation of several of its competitors. It might also be a parliament,
i.e. a representative body that acts as a public guardian of the law. Such a parliament
would sit only as a court of law. It does not have the power to govern or to make laws
that restrict anybodys rights. However, it can be an effective agent of justice if
it commands sufficient authority to convince the public that the courts of law or police
forces that it convicts, are not worthy of the publics trust (thereby destroying
their economic base), or to bring about a collective effort of other organisations of
justice to enforce its verdicts against recalcitrant convicts.
Because the courts in a kritarchy need the consent of all parties if they wish to avoid
the risk of using violence against an innocent person, they need to offer sufficient
guarantees of competence and impartiality. They need to do so both to elicit the
cooperation of the accused and defendants, and to assure the plaintiffs and claimants, who
initiate the proceedings, that their verdicts are unlikely to be contested in another
court. Short of seeking a monopoly by the violent elimination of its competitors, an
organisation of justice has no alternative but to build up a solid reputation for justice.
Working out the details, conventions and protocols for an operational efficient system
of justice is no mean task. Like every other significant practical undertaking it involves
knowledge of the general principles of law as well as experimentation with different types
of organisation for the supply of justice. It is the task of applying entrepreneurial
creativity to recombine available social, technical, administrative and financial
resources and skills so as to improve the outlook for effective justice. It is not likely
that this task can be carried out with any consistency within the stifling confines a
legal monopoly. On this conviction, the case for kritarchy rests.