Ius sine lege
::Pages::
Home
Contact
Books
Texts
Teaching
Links
By the way
::Introductions::
The Law
Logic
Natural Law
Computer engineer?
My son's website
Last update
2004-12-06
(C) 2004
Frank van Dun
Gent, België
| |
Home
|
NATURAL LAW
|
SECTION
1
The concept of natural
law
Theory and praxis
The natural law of mankind
Nature and convention
Current neglect of natural law
Positive law
The caricature of
natural law
Rationalising injustice
Natural law
and morality
SECTION
2
Natural rights
|
The concept of natural law
The word 'law' means order, hence natural law is simply the
natural order. In the sense in which natural law is relevant to jurists, it is
the natural order of persons -- specifically, the order of natural persons: human beings
that are capable of rational, purposive action, speech and thought. In short,
natural law is the natural order of the human world.
Laws are patterns of order. Hence, natural laws are
patterns of natural order -- and, in the juristically relevant sense, patterns
of order among natural persons.
Theory
and praxis of natural law
A student of natural law studies the natural order of the
human world. His primary theoretical objective is to discover and to identify
the natural laws of the human world -- in short, it is to answer the question
'What is the natural law?' Clearly, that theoretical objective implies no positive or
negative valuation of that order -- its purpose is not to argue that the
natural law ought to be respected. The theoretical study of natural law is a 'value-free'
undertaking.
Of course, not only jurists but also economists,
anthropologists, and practitioners of other scientific disciplines as well,
study the patterns of order in the human world. However, whereas, for example,
economists focus on how orderly patterns of coordinated actions emerge in the
human world, jurists focus on the order of persons as such. Their concern is
with the conditions in which human persons can be and are
distinguished properly from one another and from other things. By implication, they are
also concerned with the conditions in which persons are or are likely to be
confused with one another or with other things.
The primary practical objective of the juristic
study of natural law is to
propose rules or practical principles that, if followed by human beings, are
likely to maintain, strengthen and restore respect for the natural order of the human
world. They are the principles and rules of justice. The word 'justice' literally means
that which is conducive to ius. Like the word 'law' itself, 'ius' denotes the
natural order of persons that are capable of solemn speech (Latin iurare, French
jurer), of undertaking and honoring commitments and agreements (which are
also called iura). In short, justice
is the art of
making law (Latin ius) prevail.
Of course, the practical objective of the juristic
study of natural law presupposes not only that we [can] know what the order of the human world is
but also that it is a respectable order -- one that people ought to
respect. In its practical aspect, the study of natural law is not a
'value-free' undertaking. A significant part of the philosophy of natural law
concerns analysis and evaluation of arguments that set out to prove or to
disprove the statement that people ought to respect the natural law.
The most obvious (and to most people for all practical
purposes sufficient) reason why we ought to respect the natural law
primarily involves the fact that not doing so usually causes immediate harm or loss to some innocent people and is likely in the long rum
to be harmful to many more. The harm results from the fact that in not
respecting the natural law one fails to distinguish properly between persons
and other things, or between one person and another.
Note, however, that the assumption of the respectability of
the natural law is compatible with the assumption that not respecting the
natural law may, and often does, benefit those who do not respect it and
perhaps others as well. However, unlike the utilitarian philosophers, the
natural lawyers make a distinction between, on the one hand, justly or lawfully acquired
benefits and justly or lawfully suffered harms and, on
the other hand, benefits
acquired and harms suffered as a consequence of unjust or unlawful actions.
They can do this if the distinctions between persons, and between persons and
other things are objective--which is something that few people doubt.
Opponents of natural law believe that there is no natural order of the
human world or else that it is not a respectable order. Hence, they see no
reason why they (or anybody else) should respect the distinctions that define
that order.
The natural law of the human world
There is nothing mysterious about the
natural law of the human world. To repeat, it is the order of natural persons -- human beings that are capable of rational, purposive action, speech and thought.
Each one of us by nature is an element of the human world and each one us by
nature is capable of
doing, thinking and saying things, independently of what others are doing,
thinking and saying at the same time. This independence marks each one of us
as a separate person. It is true, of course, that people depend on others for
many things and that we generally can succeed in what we do only with
the passive or active cooperation of others. However, that cooperation is
never automatic. It must be willed. It can be given or withheld. It implies
our existence as separate persons, as individual personalities.
The separateness of human persons is the natural law of the
human world, the fundamental fact
as far as our life as rational
beings is concerned. It is fundamental to our biology, psychology and
praxeology--to our lives, thoughts, feelings, and actions.
However, the fact that we are rational does not guarantee that we are reasonable persons.
It also does not guarantee that we always act and speak justly. We can think, speak and act
reasonably and justly, in ways
that respect the fundamental given of our existence as separate persons. We
also can think, speak and act unreasonably and unjustly, in ways that inadvertently or purposively fail to
respect it.
If we do not respect the fact of our existence as separate
persons then we create disorder in the human world. This happens, for example,
when we try to obfuscate our true identity, leading others to believe that
what we say or do are the words or deeds of others. It happens when we try to
obfuscate the true identity of another person to lead
others to believe that his or her words or actions were really our own. It
happens when we unilaterally take another's work and make it appear that it
was our own. It happens when we act towards another as if he or
she were not a person at all but a thing or animal that we may use unilaterally as a means
or resource for our own ends. It happens most clearly when we treat
another as a mere object that we may hit or hurt at our own pleasure. It also happens,
and on a large scale, in
most political societies that practice the arts of taking from some to give to
others and of burdening or crippling some to give others a 'competitive
advantage'.
Actions of that kind create disorder in the human world
because they make it difficult -- and, unless stopped and undone fairly
quickly, even impossible -- to tell who said,
did or produced what. They prevent us from correctly assigning responsibility or
liability, praise or
blame, by obfuscating the difference between the producer and the parasite, the
felon and his victim, the agent and the patient, the guilty and the innocent,
the debtor and the creditor, and so on. In short, they interfere, sometimes
intentionally, with the data that are essential to the working of our 'moral
compass'.
Such actions are rightly called unlawful and also injustices, because they
deny or aim to deny to another what is rightly his -- in particular, of course,
his existence and identity as a person. Indeed, the two
main kinds of injustices are, first, treating a person as not a person
at all and, second, treating him as if he were someone else.
On the other hand, when we do respect the basic fact of our
existence as separate persons, we maintain the order of the human world in
what we do and say. No
person is mistaken for a mere thing or animal; no person is mistaken for
another. Then,
we make sure that we can attribute every word, every action, every product to
its true author or owner. In doing that, we are acting justly. In the words of
a great Roman jurist, we attribute to each what is rightly his.
Basic patterns of order in the human world are respect
for other persons and their property (see also Natural
rights), and as an immediate consequence, the
assumption of personal responsibility and liability for one's own acts whether
they occur in the course of the execution of agreements (contracts) or not.
Human actions that conform to those patterns avoid and forestall the
confusion about persons that is the essence of injustice. Justice, to
repeat, is concerned with devising principles, rules and methods of action the
application of which ensures that conformity or seeks to restore it when
there have been deviations.
It follows that while justice requires us to respect other
persons, it also requires us to act against those who by their unlawful acts
fail to respect others. That does not mean the requirements of justice are
contradictory. A person who inadvertently or in a temporary fit violates the
natural law can always volunteer to undo his transgression or to submit
to a procedure of arbitration to determine the kind and amount of restitution
he owes to another. No violent action against such a tort-feasor is
necessary.
However, one who refuses to undo his transgression and
instead willfully and knowingly retains something that belongs to his victim
and seeks to 'flee from justice' thereby announces that he wants to be outside
the law. He announces that he does not want to be part of the world of human
persons but wants to be a criminal, an indiscriminating person who refuses to
recognize the separate and independent existence of his victim. He maintains a
situation in which it is impossible for the victim (or one of his lawful
successors) to have and enjoy what is rightly his without doing violence to
the criminal. Consequently, the victims (or their lawful successors) do not
commit an injustice when they use violence and force against a criminal to the
extent that is necessary to restore respect for law.
Nature
and convention
Because the principles of justice apply to human beings as such,
they are as valid for those who happen to occupy the social position of a
king, a ruler or a politician as they are for those who occupy the social
position of a subject, a servant or a citizen. Generally, the demands of justice are
independent of one's social position, role or function. They are demands on
natural persons, whatever their social status, whether they have a social
status or not. Moreover, the demands that justice makes on you are the same
whether the persons with whom you are dealing are, or are not, members of any
social group to which you belong -- whether they are acquaintances or
strangers.
To make the same point in different words, natural law is
not the order of any society or social organization (in
Dutch maatschappij); it is not concerned with the complex and often
fanciful social distinctions of status or position, role or function that
characterize such an organization. Rather, it is the order
of conviviality (literally, the order of living together, cf. Dutch samenleving)
of people as people.
The conditions of conviviality are universal, independent
of time and place; they are the same here and now as they were in Ancient
China or Ancient Greece. The reason is that conviviality is a relation between
natural persons, and human nature is not different here and now from what it
was there and then. Of course, some and perhaps most of our customs and
regulations here and now are very different from the customs and the
regulations of those ancient civilizations in any period of their existence.
So are our clothes and tools. But none of those things has any bearing on the
natural law or the conditions of conviviality that the rules and principles of
justice aim to preserve. They are conventional things, not natural things --
and, as already the Greek Sophists of Antiquity pointed out, it is a grave
mistake to confuse nature and convention, or the relative notions of legality
or social conformism and the universal notion of justice. It is sensible to
demand that our customs, regulations and conventions conform to the
requirements of justice. To demand that we derive our notion of justice from
our social conventions is like insisting that we derive the proportions of a
healthy body from the clothes in our wardrobe.
Unlike the natural law, which is in the nature of things
and therefore unaffected by desire or opinion, social orders are always
conventional. They reflect what at least some people at a particular time and
place want, hope for and fear, and how they think they can achieve their goals
and avoid what they perceive as dangers. The proponents of a given social
order are likely to insist on a general respect for the conventions of their
society, whether these are in accordance with principles of justice or not.
However, as even a cursory knowledge of history soon will reveal, few
conventions can stand the test of time. With changing circumstances,
knowledge, technologies, sources of wealth, ambitions, opinions and beliefs,
not only the support for but also the raison d'être of particular
conventions may wax or wane. Evidently, the factors of social change may well
affect also the support of various groups in society for the principles of
justice, but they do not, and cannot, affect the raison d'être of
those principles.
Throughout history, many societies have perfected the art
of organizing injustice by the skilful application of techniques of human
resources management: punishments and rewards, intimidation, threats and
promises, propaganda and indoctrination. To most members of those societies,
the injustice of their conventional life is thereby hidden from view -- at
least it is a taboo, which it is dangerous to question in public. However,
outsiders, contemplating such societies from a safe distance in space or time,
readily can see the injustice of their conventions. We need not be
specialists in the social organization of Ancient Rome to know that Roman
slavery was a paradigm of injustice, but unless we have some knowledge of
Roman Law, we have no way of knowing whether it was legal or not.
Current neglect of natural law
Nowadays, the study of natural law virtually has been
banned from the training of lawyers. What remains of it in the academic
curriculum of most law schools is no more than a little bit of
'intellectual history', which is devoted mainly to the works of a handful of
ancient, medieval and early modern writers and philosophers. Often,
students get the impression that natural law is something that can be found
only in books (in the same way that statutory law, the verdicts of courts and
international treaties are mere texts). They are led to believe that the
natural law is nothing but a collection of theories of natural law. It is not.
Nor, of course, is the physical universe nothing but a collection of theories
of physics.
The practice of
natural law also has been eliminated almost completely by the legal profession. Very
often, the study and the practice of natural law are scorned if not ridiculed.
The reasons for this desultory attitude towards natural law
are many. One reason is ideological. Many people subscribe to an ideology that
is virulently anti-human. They do not think that there is anything respectable
about human beings as they are. Usually, they combine this belief with the
idea that 'human nature can and should be changed' so as to make it conform
to their own ideal of Man. Thus, they claim that men and women should be taught or forced not to respect the order of human
world but to respect instead the imaginary 'normative order' that the ideologues
prefer. They should be forced or taught not to respect one another for
the human beings they are but only the ideal 'new man' that they should
become.
However, the most important reason for the negative
attitude is that the legal profession has
discovered that there is much more money to be made from focusing on highly
politicized complex, constantly changing systems of social regulation than it
ever could hope to make from the study and practice of natural law.
In the
present condition of civilization, people generally have more to fear from
their government than from occasional acts of criminality or negligence
committed by their likes. In the course of history, states have monopolized
rule-enforcement within their territories. Not surprisingly, they have given
more attention to enforcing their own regulations than to enforcing the rules of
justice. After all, the purpose of a state is not the enforcement of the rules
of justice but making people comply with its own demands and
regulations. Moreover, if states were really intent on eradicating
injustice then they would achieve by far the greatest part of their purpose by
eradicating themselves -- for whatever it is states generally do, respecting
persons or their property is no part of it.
Justice, then, is only an accidental and often marginal
concern of the state. On the other hand, legality or conformity to the rules
it imposes or wants to be obeyed is its central concern. (The
word 'legality' derives from the Latin lex, which denotes a general
command issued by a public authority, which originally was a military authority.)
Understandably, in such circumstances, people are willing to pay more for
advice on how to keep the government and its agents off their backs and on
their side than for advice on seeking justice. Unlike the basic principles of justice, which any person
with a modicum of common sense can discover for himself, social regulations
are merely what other people say they are. The only way to get to know the
regulations is to pay close attention to what those others are saying. Few
people have the time or the inclination to do that; most of them are willing
to pay for information and advice about such regulations if and when they need
it.
Lawyers have responded to that situation by abandoning
the study and practice of law and becoming specialists in current social
regulation. However, rather than admit as much openly, they generally have
tended to redefine the word 'law' so that it now is virtually synonymous with
politically imposed or sanctioned social regulation.
Positive law
'Law', indeed, now usually refers to some national system of social
regulation -- a system of social regulation imposed by the rulers of a
nation-state and otherwise coordinated by their agents and servants. By extension,
'law' now refers also to
regulatory systems to which the rulers and diplomatic agents of
various nation-states have agreed. All of this goes under the academic label
of 'positive law', which covers any one of the many particular imposed
('posited') systems of regulation by legal rules that we find in various
politically organized societies.
Positive
law consists of the elements of such a system, for example its
legislative, executive, administrative, judiciary and military and police 'organs', its offices and officers, the rules
they follow and apply, and the decisions they make. Those systems have no
necessary connection with natural law or justice. They define only what
is legal in a particular society, not what is lawful among human beings.
The positive law is not the
natural order of the human world. It is the artificial order that some
powerful people (individuals and groups) in a particular society currently try to impose on others. It is an
order, not of relations among human persons as such, but of relations among
social positions, roles and functions. Thus the positive law of a particular
country tells us what powers, immunities, rights, duties, claims and liabilities
legally attach
to the social positions, roles and functions of a general, a minister, a representative of the people, a
citizen, a registered alien, a pensioner, a police man, and so on. In the
same way, the rules of chess tell us what a king, queen, knight, pawn
or other piece is or can or cannot do.
Like a king or queen in chess, a general, citizen or police
officer is not a natural person but a position or function in a
particular sort of game (usually and grandiloquently referred to as 'a social
system'). Typically, the position is occupied and the function performed
by a human natural person but that need not be the case. It is a grave mistake
to confuse the position with its occupant. Whatever the positive law [of this or that country] may tell us
about what a citizen is, or can or cannot do, it tells
us nothing about what a human person who happens to fill that position at a
given moment is or what he or she can or cannot do.
Positive law, then, pertains primarily to 'artificial
persons', to social positions,
roles and functions within a particular social organization, especially one
that is imposed by a state or a group of states. It pertains to human beings
only indirectly, to the extent that they are supposed to supply the physical and intellectual
labor that those positions require.
In other words, it pertains to human beings as means or resources for organizing social activity.
However, it is conceivable -- in some cases, it already is
a fact -- that automated machines take the place
of human suppliers of socially required labor. Conceivably, a social organization could develop so that it becomes independent of the availability
of human persons to supply particular skills. Then human beings are reduced to
the status of mere objects to which social action can be
applied. If and when that happens the
relations between human individuals and 'society' are analogous to the
relations between cattle and a farmer or between a collection of pets and
their caretaker. Such an outcome is in fact the wish of [philosophical] socialists, who accept
at least one and usually both of the following propositions: 1) Individuals
belong to society, which therefore has the right to make them obey its
prescriptions; 2) Society should take care of individuals because individuals
are incapable of decently managing their own lives and affairs.
Positive law, when taken to its logical socialist extreme, is the scheme by means of which 'society' manages its
human and other resources, analogous to the schemes a farmer uses to
manage or take care of his human and other resources.
It follows that positive law has no logical or necessary
connection with human life and action. The concept of 'positive law', as noted
before, is the concept of an artificial order -- an order of artificial
persons.
However, no matter how much social regulation there may be,
as long as human nature is what it is and always has been, the search for
knowledge and understanding of the natural order of the
human world remains a valid objective.
The
positivists' caricature of natural law
Regrettably, students nowadays get most of their
information about natural law from positivists, whose understanding of it is
virtually nil. For the positivists, as we have seen, 'law' denotes a set of
legal rules and associated juridical verdicts and administrative decisions.
Positive law, for them, is such a set -- namely, one that is currently
effectively 'posited' (imposed, adhered to by the rulers and their followers
in a given society). Consequently, positivists can only think of natural law
as another set of rules, verdicts and decisions -- namely, one that is
not 'posited' by the authorities in a given society but by some mythical,
supernatural or impersonal imagined authority (God, Nature, Reason, or
what have you).
Thus, the positivists think of natural law as an alternative
system of rules, verdicts and decisions that supposedly applies to, or
regulates, the same things as does the positive law. This is a serious
mistake.
Rules, verdicts or decisions are things one can obey or
disobey. However, to say that one can obey or disobey the natural law makes no
sense at all. The natural law, as noted before, is an order of things (in
particular, an order of persons). Such an order one cannot obey or disobey.
One only can respect it or fail to respect it. Now, respecting an order of
things does not imply obeying that order -- no more than respecting a
person implies obeying that person; no more than respecting an old building
implies obeying that building.
To repeat, the natural law is the natural order, the order
of conviviality of natural persons. It is not concerned with any artificial
order (say, the order of kings, queens, knights, pawns, etcetera in the
'social system' of chess, or
the order of presidents, members of the cabinet, secretaries of state, MP's,
or citizens in the 'game' of some State).
The natural law and the positive law are not alternative
systems of rules that apply to the same thing. The natural law is the
law of natural persons and positive law is a law of artificial persons. Thus,
natural law and positive law relate to different things. Therefore, a
conflict between natural law and positive law is conceivable only because the artificial persons of
the positive law are no more than social positions, roles
and functions that -- at least for the time being -- happen to be occupied, or performed, by natural persons. Even
so, there is a real conflict only for those intellectual and moral weaklings
who derive their self-esteem from their identification with their social
position. A mature adult is supposed to know the difference between the real
world and the games people play, between the natural and the artificial. He or
she is supposed to be able to keep such things in perspective.
Rationalising
injustice
An old but adequate definition of the natural law of the human
world is that it is an order of freedom among likes. Human beings are free (in
the sense of separateness and independence that we noted above) and they are
all alike (in the sense of being members of the same natural species).
The practical objective of the student of natural law is to
instill respect for that order of freedom among likes -- that is, to instill
the sense and practice of justice. That respect obviously has personal costs because
in many circumstances a
person or group can profit enormously from not respecting other persons or
their property. On many occasions, crime, dishonesty, fraud and shifting the
blame do pay -- sometimes handsomely, especially when they are organized
on a large scale.
Justice often requires that you do not do what you have the power to
do. Thus, the powerful and the influential, be they individuals, groups or
organizations, usually find justice to be a
hindrance to the realization of their designs. The same is true, on a
theoretical level, for many ideologues and idealists. They understand that the
implementation of their ideas and ideals for 'another and better world' would
be virtually impossible if it had to conform to the requirements of justice --
if they had to respect not only the different ideas and ideals but also the
skepticism of others.
Here, we can see part of the point of H.L.Mencken's famous saying that
'Injustice is relative easy to bear; it is justice that stings'. Justice, if
rigorously enforced, deprives the powerful, the ideologues and the idealists
of much of the possibilities for enacting their schemes. Justice, if cherished
as an objective value, stands as a forceful rebuke of the self-congratulation
with which such people usually propose their plans and projects.
Clearly, many people have a strong interest in 'debunking
justice', that is, in 'rationalizing injustice'. (Usually, of course, this
debunking takes the form of 'redefining' justice as something else than
justice: few are willing to forego the prestige that the word 'justice' has
accumulated throughout the ages.)
Because justice is respect for the order of freedom among
likes, debunking justice proceeds by attacking the respectability of either
freedom or likeness ('equality'). This can be done in either of two ways:
* 1) by arguing that freedom (the separateness or
independence of persons) or equality (the likeness of persons) does not exist,
that it is at best an illusion that can be dispelled by adopting some 'true
metaphysical system'; or
* 2) by arguing that freedom or equality, though an actual property of human
persons, is not a respectable property, perhaps even a dangerous one.
Thus, Plato (and a long line of political thinkers after
him) argued that likeness (equality) was a fact, but that people ought to be
taught that it was not, lest they refuse to accept the different benefits and
burdens that come with different positions in a politically organized society.
Aristotle, on the other hand, argued that likeness is but a superficial
illusion. Thus, he taught that there is no true likeness between Greeks and
barbarians and that consequently there was nothing wrong with the superior
Greeks holding other inferior people as slaves.
Rousseau (and many socialists after him) maintained that
human freedom was a fact of nature but that people should be taught to believe
that it is dangerous and that they ought to renounce their human nature in
favor of the artificial condition of citizenship. In that condition,
everybody is supposed to be a creature, not of nature, but of the laws (leges)
enacted
by the state (which is but name of the collectivity of citizens). In
short, natural persons should become artificial persons, that is citizens --
wittingly or unwittingly, willingly or
by legal compulsion.
Marx, on the other hand, appealed to the much more radical
idea of universal socialism. He claimed that no human being is free but that only the
human species can be free. As far as individuals are concerned, freedom is an
illusion. Hence, it can not justify any claim. However, those who identify
themselves with humanity as a whole are universal individuals. As 'species-beings',
who know themselves to be identical with the
human race, they are the true communists. As such, they represent a superior evolution of mankind. They
should not be deterred by the illusions of morality and justice of those who
still are mired in the false consciousness of their particular individuality.
Politicians and power-seekers have little use for
the metaphysical systems underlying such attempts to debunk natural law and justice.
However, they usually are more than willing to refer to the prestige of such
systems among
intellectuals to justify attempts to impose systems of regulation that are in
flagrant violation of the principles of justice.
A potent motive for debunking justice in the Western world
stems from the fact that justice is central to the Christian outlook on the
human condition. With the rise of anti-Christian and anticlerical movements in
Europe, many people have been led to extend their sometimes valid criticism of
Christian theologies and Church practices to everything the Christian
tradition stands for -- especially its commitment to justice as the primary
virtue of human relations.
Sometimes this criticism extends even farther, amounting to
a debunking of every moral notion whatsoever, whether Christian or not. Hence, many have
been led to espouse the ideology that mankind must be liberated from 'the
shackles of morality' and be taught to live 'beyond good and evil' or beyond
'freedom and dignity'. The argument suggests that this would be for the good
of Man -- not, course, for his 'moral' good but for his 'utilitarian' good,
the satisfaction of his desires.
By making the satisfaction of desire the supreme good of
Man, such views provide justification for the idea that others may be
sacrificed and coercively regulated whenever they stand in the way of what one
believes to be desirable for Man -- or, to use the fashionable euphemism, in
the way of Man's democratically expressed
desires. However, because this 'Man' is not a real individual but merely a
statistical construct, those views tend to reduce human individuals to a
statistic for use in some (usually unspecified) calculus of utility-maximization.
Natural
law and morality
One of the major positivistic critiques of natural law theory is that
it confuses law and morality. Indeed, there is a close connection between natural law and
morality, but it is not the sort of connection that positivists take for
granted.
As we have seen, in its practical aspect, the
study of natural law assumes that people ought to respect the natural order
and consequently ought to abide by the principles and rules of justice.
According to the positivist critique, this supposedly amounts to a confusion
of law and morality. It does not.
As with social conventions and regulations, it makes sense to
demand that one's morality conform to the natural order of the human world.
It does not make sense to demand that the natural order of the human world
conform to one's moral convictions.
The truth is that a morality (or moral theory) that is not predicated on
respect for the natural order of the human world must condone injustice and
therefore reasonably cannot claim to have universal validity. Thieves, robbers, conquistadors,
politicians -- all of them may develop a morality of their own and take great
pride in it (as, supposedly, mafiosi take great pride in their code of honor),
but one hardly can expect their victims and subjects to share their feelings
for it.
Respect for the natural law is a precondition of morality.
This is not to say that because there is only one natural law there can be no
more than one morality. On the contrary, there may be any number of different
moralities, all of which are compatible with respect for the natural law.
To understand this, keep in mind that the purpose of a
morality is to direct a person in living 'a good life'. Obviously, no person
can discover what the good life for him is except through the actual
experience of his life, his personality and circumstances. The knowledge of
those things is not innate. Because of its purpose, a morality is
'agent-relative'. If it is carefully constructed on the basis of relevant
facts about a person, his life and circumstances, it is objectively valid for that person, but not
necessarily for any other. At the limit, every person may have his or
her own true 'moral theory'. However, all of those moralities must presuppose
the respectability of the same natural law, if they are to be at all valid.
One that does not necessarily will direct a person to be unjust towards
others. It cannot be a respectable moral theory and therefore will not be able
to lend
any weight to claims and arguments that are based on it.
Moreover, respect for the natural law is a necessary
condition for learning how to be moral. One's experience by itself
does not tell one whether, or to what extent, one's ideas on how to navigate
the sea of life are compatible with the ideas of others. In that regard, a
person's experience is
instructive only when the natural law is respected -- when there is a
reasonable amount of order in the human world. Then, people can be
reasonably sure that they face, and have to give accounts for, the consequences
of all, and only, their own words and actions.
Where the natural law is not respected, there is confusion
about who did, produced or said what. Then people have
no way of knowing whether they are doing well by doing good or by doing evil,
or whether they are doing badly despite doing good. Only experience can tell
them whether they are doing well or badly; but only when their experiments in
living are not contaminated by confusion about who said, did, or produced
what, can they learn much from the results of their own words, actions and
work.
Thus, where the natural law is not respected,
responsibility and liability are likely to be directed to the wrong persons.
Consequently, bad (irresponsible, hence immoral) behavior is likely to
generate undue rewards, while good (responsible, hence moral) behavior is
likely to remain fruitless. Under such conditions, being a responsible, moral
person 'does not pay' while irresponsibility and immorality are, as it were,
subsidized.
Social organizations often are set up expressly to divert
and even dissipate responsibility and liability. That is particularly true in
political societies. For example, in democratic states, the responsibility and
liability for the actions and decisions of ruling politicians are diverted to
something called 'the voter', 'the electorate' or 'the citizen'. However, if
we try to pin liability on 'the voter' we immediately discover that the rules
of the democratic game do not permit us to do so. Responsibility and liability
are dissipated completely. There is nothing in the rules of the voting
game that might discourage people from acting irresponsibly. In their
political roles, they are encouraged to act as if they owed respect to no
one.
To take another example: under present institutional
arrangements, decisions of a few central bankers (in the American Federal
Reserve System , the European Central Bank, or the Bank of
Japan) have repercussions on
the lives and fortunes of hundreds of millions of people. Yet, they are not
liable for what they do. As long as they stay within the rules of the game,
they have the 'perfect excuse' of 'only doing their job'. As for the
politicians who organized that game and created the positions of those
monetary potentates in the first place, they also have a 'perfect excuse': the
central bank is 'independent'. Having been socialized, money -- which is
the medium of exchange and the primary condition of coordination among large
numbers of people -- now is divorced completely from the natural law and hence
from moral life.
Bibliographical note:
For a detailed analysis of the concept of an
order of [natural] persons, see The
Logic of Law (djvu) and Natural
Law, a Logical Analysis (pdf).
For more on the distinction between artificial social
orders ('societies') and the natural convivial order, see The
Lawful and The Legal (html).
|
|
|
|