LYSANDER SPOONER
Lysander Spooner (1808-1887) was a practising lawyer and businessman in Massachussetts. He
was an ardent individualist, who attacked all sorts of government activities, such as the
postal monopoly, and opposed slavery on the ground that it was unconstitutional and in
conflict with natural law. He was a strong proponent of a naturalistic approach to natural
law, which is the order of peaceful coexistence among human beings.
Below you will find a copy of the text of Spooner's tract on Natural
Law as well as of his celebrated text on the American constitution: No Treason, The Constitution of No Authority.
Chapter I.
The Science of Justice.
Section I.
The science of mine and thine---the science of justice---is the science
of all human rights; of all a man's rights of person and property; of all his rights to
life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.
It is the science which alone can tell any man what he can, and cannot,
do; what he can, and cannot, have; what he can, and cannot, say, without infringing the
rights of any other person.
It is the science of peace; and the only science of peace; since it is
the science which alone can tell us on what conditions mankind can live in peace, or ought
to live in peace, with each other.
These conditions are simply these: viz., first, that each man shall do,
towards every other, all that justice requires him to do; as, for example, that he shall
pay his debts, that he shall return borrowed or stolen property to its owner, and that he
shall make reparation for any injury he may have done to the person or property of
another.
The second condition is, that each man shall abstain from doing to
another, anything which justice forbids him to do; as, for example, that he shall abstain
from committing theft, robbery, arson, murder, or any other crime against the person or
property of another.
So long as these conditions are fulfilled, men are at peace, and ought
to remain at peace, with each other. But when either of these conditions is violated, men
are at war. And they must necessarily remain at war until justice is re-established.
Through all time, so far as history informs us, wherever mankind have
attempted to live in peace with each other, both the natural instincts, and the collective
wisdom of the human race, have acknowledged and prescribed, as an indispensable condition,
obedience to this one only universal obligation: viz., that each should live honestly
towards every other.
The ancient maxim makes the sum of a man's legal duty to his fellow men
to be simply this: "to live honestly, to hurt no one, to give to every one his
due."
This entire maxim is really expressed in the single words, to live
honestly; since to live honestly is to hurt no one, and give to every one his due.
Section II.
Man, no doubt, owes many other moral duties to his fellow men; such as
to feed the hungry, clothe the naked, shelter the homeless, care for the sick, protect the
defenceless, assist the weak, and enlighten the ignorant. But these are simply moral
duties, of which each man must be his own judge, in each particular case, as to whether,
and how, and how far, he can, or will, perform them. But of his legal duty---that is, of
his duty to live honestly towards his fellow men---his fellow men not only may judge, but,
for their own protection, must judge. And, if need be, they may rightfully compel him to
perform it. They may do this, acting singly, or in concert. They may do it on the instant,
as the necessity arises, or deliberately and systematically, if they prefer to do so, and
the exigency will admit of it.
Section III.
Although it is the right of anybody and everybody---of any one man, or
set of men, no less than another---to repel injustice, and compel justice, for themselves,
and for all who may be wronged, yet to avoid the errors that are liable to result from
haste and passion, and that everybody, who desires it, may rest secure in the assurance of
protection, without a resort to force, it is evidently desirable that men should
associate, so far as they freely and voluntarily can do so, for the maintenance of justice
among themselves, and for mutual protection against other wrong-doers. It is also in the
highest degree desirable that they should agree upon some plan or system of judicial
proceedings, which, in the trial of causes, should secure caution, deliberation, thorough
investigation, and, as far as possible, freedom from every influence but the simple desire
to do justice.
Yet such associations can be rightful and desirable only in so far as
they are purely voluntary. No man can rightfully be coerced into joining one, or
supporting one, against his will. His own interest, his own judgement, and his own
conscience alone must determine whether he will join this association, or that; or whether
he will join any. If he chooses to depend, for the protection of his own rights, solely
upon himself, and upon such voluntary assistance as other persons may freely offer to him
when the necessity for it arises, he has a perfect right to do so. And this course would
be a reasonably safe one for him to follow, so long as he himself should manifest the
ordinary readiness of mankind, in like cases, to go to the assistance and defence of
injured persons; and should also himself "live honestly, hurt no one, and give to
every one his due." For such a man is reasonably sure of always giving friends and
defenders enough in case of need, whether he shall have joined any association, or not.
Certainly no man can rightfully be required to join, or support, an
association whose protection he does not desire. Nor can any man be reasonably or
rightfully expected to join, or support, any association whose plans, or method of
proceeding, he does not approve, as likely to accomplish its professed purpose of
maintaining justice, and at the same time itself avoid doing injustice. To join, or
support, one that would, in his opinion, be inefficient, would be absurd. To join or
support one that, in his opinion, would itself do injustice, would be criminal. He must,
therefore, be left at the same liberty to join, or not to join, an association for this
purpose, as for any other, according as his own interest, discretion, or conscience shall
dictate.
An association for mutual protection against injustice is like an
association for mutual protection against fire or shipwreck. And there is no more right or
reason in compelling any man to join or support one of these associations, against his
will, his judgement, or his conscience, than there is in compelling him to join or support
any other, whose benefits (if it offer any) he does not want, or whose purposes or methods
he does not approve.
Section IV.
No objection can be made to these voluntary associations upon the ground
that they would lack that knowledge of justice, as a science, which would be necessary to
enable them to maintain justice, and themselves avoid doing injustice. Honesty, justice,
natural law, is usually a very plain and simple matter, easily understood by common minds.
Those who desire to know what it is, in any particular case, seldom have to go far to find
it. It is true, it must be learned, like any other science. But it is also true that it is
very easily learned. Although as illimitable in its applications as the infinite relations
and dealings of men with each other, it is, nevertheless, made up of a few simple
elementary principles, of the truth and justice of which every ordinary mind has an almost
intuitive perception. And almost all men have the same perceptions of what constitutes
justice, or of what justice requires, when they understand alike the facts from which
their inferences are to be drawn.
Men living in contact with each other, and having intercourse together,
cannot avoid learning natural law, to a very great extent, even if they would. The
dealings of men with men, their separate possessions and their individual wants, and the
disposition of every man to demand, and insist upon, whatever he believes to be his due,
and to resent and resist all invasions of what he believes to be his rights, are
continually forcing upon their minds the questions, Is this act just? or is it unjust? Is
this thing mine? or is it his? And these are questions of natural law; questions which, in
regard to the great mass of cases, are answered alike by the human mind everywhere.
[Spooner's note: Sir William Jones, an English judge in India, and one of the most learned
judges that ever lived, learned in Asiatic as well as European law, says: "It is
pleasing to remark the similarity, or, rather, the idenity, of those conclusions which
pure, unbiased reason, to all ages and nations, seldom fails to draw, in such juridical
inquiries as are not fettered and manacled by positive institutions."---jones on
bailments, 133. He means here to say that, when no law has been made in violation of
justice, judicial tribunals, "in all ages and nations," have "seldom"
failed to agree as to what justice is.]
Children learn the fundamental principles of natural law at a very early
age. Thus they very early understand that one child must not, without just cause, strike
or otherwise hurt, another; that one child must not assume any arbitrary control or
domination over another; that one child must not, either by force, deceit, or stealth,
obtain possession of anything that belongs to another; that if one child commits any of
these wrongs against another, it is not only the right of the injured child to resist,
and, if need be, punish the wrongdoer, and compel him to make reparation, but that it is
also the right, and the moral duty, of all other children, and all other persons, to
assist the injured party in defending his rights, and redressing his wrongs. These are
fundamental principles of natural law, which govern the most important transactions of man
with man. Yet children learn them earlier than they learn that three and three are six, or
five and five ten. Their childish plays, even, could not be carried on without a constant
regard to them; and it is equally impossible for persons of any age to live together in
peace on any other conditions.
It would be no extravagance to say that, in most cases, if not in all,
mankind at large, young and old, learn this natural law long before they have learned the
meanings of the words by which we describe it. In truth, it would be impossible to make
them understand the real meanings of the words, if they did not understand the nature of
the thing itself. To make them understand the meanings of the words justice and injustice
before knowing the nature of the things themselves, would be as impossible as it would be
to make them understand the meanings of the words heat and cold, wet and dry, light and
darkness, white and black, one and two, before knowing the nature of the things
themselves. Men necessarily must know sentiments and ideas, no less than material things,
before they can know the meanings of the words by which we describe them.
Chapter II.
The Science of Justice (Continued)
Section I.
If justice be not a natural principle, it is no principle at all. If it
be not a natural principle, there is no such thing as justice. If it be not a natural
principle, all that men have ever said or written about it, from time immemorial, has been
said and written about that which had no existence. If it be not a natural principle, all
the appeals for justice that have ever been heard, and all the struggles for justice that
have ever been witnessed, have been appeals and struggles for a mere fantasy, a vagary of
the imagination, and not for a reality.
If justice be not a natural principle, then there is no such thing as
injustice; and all the crimes of which the world has been the scene, have been no crimes
at all; but only simple events, like the falling of the rain, or the setting of the sun;
events of which the victims had no more reason to complain than they had to complain of
the running of the streams, or the growth of vegetation.
If justice be not a natural principle, governments (so-called) have no
more right or reason to take cognizance of it, or to pretend or profess to take cognizance
of it, than they have to take cognizance, or to pretend or profess to take cognizance, of
any other nonentity; and all their professions of establishing justice, or of maintaining
justice, or of rewarding justice, are simply the mere gibberish of fools, or the frauds of
imposters.
But if justice be a natural principle, then it is necessarily an
immutable one; and can no more be changed---by any power inferior to that which
established it---than can the law of gravitation, the laws of light, the principles of
mathematics, or any other natural law or principle whatever; and all attempts or
assumptions, on the part of any man or body of men---whether calling themselves
governments, or by any other name---to set up their own commands, wills, pleasure, or
discretion, in the place of justice, as a rule of conduct for any human being, are as much
an absurdity, an usurpation, and a tyranny, as would be their attempts to set up their own
commands, wills, pleasure, or discretion in the place of any and all the physical, mental,
and moral laws of the universe.
Section II.
If there be any such principle as justice, it is, of necessity, a
natural principle; and, as such, it is a matter of science, to be learned and applied like
any other science. And to talk of either adding to, or taking from, it, by legislation, is
just as false, absurd, and ridiculous as it would be to talk of adding to, or taking from,
mathematics, chemistry, or any other science, by legislation.
Section III.
If there be in nature such a principle as justice, nothing can be added
to, or taken from, its supreme authority by all the legislation of which the entire human
race united are capable. And all the attempts of the human race, or of any portion of it,
to add to, or take from, the supreme authority of justice, in any case whatever, is of no
more obligation upon any single human being than is the idle wind.
Section IV.
If there be such a principle as justice, or natural law, it is the
principle, or law, that tells us what rights were given to every human being at his birth;
what rights are, therefore, inherent in him as a human being, necessarily remain with him
during life; and, however capable of being trampled upon, are incapable of being blotted
out, extinguished, annihilated, or separated or eliminated from his nature as a human
being, or deprived of their inherent authority or obligation.
On the other hand, if there be no such principle as justice, or natural
law, then every human being came into the world utterly destitute of rights; and coming
into the world destitute of rights, he must necessarily forever remain so. For if no one
brings any rights with him into the world, clearly no one can ever have any rights of his
own, or give any to another. And the consequence would be that mankind could never have
any rights; and for them to talk of any such things as their rights, would be to talk of
things that never had, never will have, and never can have any existence.
Section V.
If there be such a natural principle as justice, it is necessarily the
highest, and consequently the only and universal, law for all those matters to which it is
naturally applicable. And, consequently, all human legislation is simply and always an
assumption of authority and dominion, where no right of authority or dominion exists. It
is, therefore, simply and always an intrusion, an absurdity, an usurpation, and a crime.
On the other hand, if there be no such natural principle as justice,
there can be no such thing as dishonesty; and no possible act of either force or fraud,
committed by one man against the person or property of another, can be said to be unjust
or dishonest; or be complained of, or prohibited, or punished as such. In short, if there
be no such principle as justice, there can be no such acts as crimes; and all the
professions of governments, so called, that they exist, either in whole or in part, for
the punishment or prevention of crimes, are professions that they exist for the punishment
or prevention of what never existed, nor ever can exist. Such professions are therefore
confessions that, so far as crimes are concerned, governments have no occasion to exist;
that there is nothing for them to do, and that there is nothing that they can do. They are
confessions that the governments exist for the punishment and prevention of acts that are,
in their nature, simple impossibilities.
Section VI.
If there be in nature such a principle as justice, such a principle as
honesty, such principles as we describe by the words mine and thine, such principles as
men's natural rights of person and property, then we have an immutable and universal law;
a law that we can learn, as we learn any other science; a law that tells us what is just
and what is unjust, what is honest and what is dishonest, what things are mine and what
things are thine, what are my rights of person and property and what are your rights of
person and property, and where is the boundary between each and all of my rights of person
and property and each and all of your rights of person and property. And this law is the
paramount law, and the same law, over all the world, at all times, and for all peoples;
and will be the same paramount and only law, at all times, and for all peoples, so long as
man shall live upon the earth.
But if, on the other hand, there be in nature no such principle as
justice, no such principle as honesty, no such principle as men's natural rights of person
or property, then all such words as justice and injustice, honesty and dishonesty, all
such words as mine and thine, all words that signify that one thing is one man's property
and that another thing is another man's property, all words that are used to describe
men's natural rights of person or property, all such words as are used to describe
injuries and crimes, should be struck out of all human languages as having no meanings;
and it should be declared, at once and forever, that the greatest force and the greatest
frauds, for the time being, are the supreme and only laws for governing the relations of
men with each other; and that, from henceforth, all persons and combinations of
persons---those that call themselves governments, as well as all others---are to be left
free to practice upon each other all the force, and all the fraud, of which they are
capable.
Section VII.
If there be no such science as justice, there can be no science of
government; and all the rapacity and violence, by which, in all ages and nations, a few
confederated villains have obtained the mastery over the rest of mankind, reduced them to
poverty and slavery, and established what they called governments to keep them in
subjection, have been as legitimate examples of government as any that the world is ever
to see.
Section VIII.
If there be in nature such a principle as justice, it is necessarily the
only political principle there ever was, or ever will be. All the other so-called
political principles, which men are in the habit of inventing, are not principles at all.
They are either the mere conceits of simpletons, who imagine they have discovered
something better than truth, and justice, and universal law; or they are mere devices and
pretences, to which selfish and knavish men resort as means to get fame, and power, and
money.
Chapter III.
Natural Law Contrasted With Legislation.
Section I.
Natural law, natural justice, being a principle that is naturally
applicable and adequate to the rightful settlement of every possible controversy that can
arise among men; being too, the only standard by which any controversy whatever, between
man and man, can be rightfully settled; being a principle whose protection every man
demands for himself, whether he is willing to accord it to others, or not; being also an
immutable principle, one that is always and everywhere the same, in all ages and nations;
being self-evidently necessary in all times and places; being so entirely impartial and
equitable towards all; so indispensable to the peace of mankind everywhere; so vital to
the safety and welfare of every human being; being, too, so easily learned, so generally
known, and so easily maintained by such voluntary associations as all honest men can
readily and rightully form for that purpose---being such a principle as this, these
questions arise, viz.: Why is it that it does not universally, or well nigh universally,
prevail? Why is it that it has not, ages ago, been established throughout the world as the
one only law that any man, or all men, could rightfully be compelled to obey? Why is it
that any human being ever conceived that anything so self-evidently superfluous, false,
absurd, and atrocious as all legislation necessarily must be, could be of any use to
mankind, or have any place in human affairs?
Section II.
The answer is, that through all historic times, wherever any people have
advanced beyond the savage state, and have learned to increase their means of sub-sistence
by the cultivation of soil, a greater or less number of them have associated and organized
themselves as robbers, to plunder and enslave all others, who had either accumulated any
property that could be seized, or had shown, by their labor, that they could be made to
contribute to the support or pleasure of those who should enslave them.
These bands of robbers, small in number at fist, have increased their
power by uniting with each other, inventing warlike weapons, disciplining themselves, and
perfecting their organizations as military forces, and dividing their plunder (including
their captives) among themselves, either in such proportions as have been previously
agreed on, or in such as their leaders (always desirous to increase the number of their
followers) should prescribe.
The success of these bands of robbers was an easy thing, for the reason
that those whom they plundered and ensalved were comparatively defenceless; being
scattered thinly over the country; engaged wholly in trying, by rude implements and heavy
labor, to extort a subsistence from the soil; having no weapons of war, other than sticks
and stones; having no military discipline or organization, and no means of concentrating
their forces, or acting in concert, when suddenly attacked. Under these circumstances, the
only alternative left them for saving even their lives, or the lives of their families,
was to yield up not only the crops they had gathered, and the lands they had cultivated,
but themselves and their families also as slaves.
Thenceforth their fate was, as slaves, to cultivate for others the lands
they had before cultivated for themselves. Being driven constantly to their labor, wealth
slowly increased; but all went into the hands of their tyrants.
These tyrants, living solely on plunder, and on the labor of their
slaves, and applying all their energies to the seizure of still more plunder, and the
enslavement of still other defenceless persons; increasing, too, their numbers, perfecting
their organizations, and multiplying their weapons of war, they extend their conquests
until, in order to hold what they have already got, it becomes necessary for them to act
systematically, and cooperate with each other in holding their slaves in subjection.
But all this they can do only by establishing what they call a
government, and making what they call laws.
All the great governments of the world---those now existing, as well as
those that have passed away---have been of this character. They have been mere bands of
robbers, who have associated for purposes of plunder, conquest, and the enslavement of
their fellow men. And their laws, as they have called them, have been only such agreements
as they have found it necessary to enter into, in order to maintain their organizations,
and act together in plundering and enslaving others, and in securing to each his agreed
share of the spoils.
All these laws have had no more real obligation than have the agreements
which brigands, bandits, and pirates find it necessary to enter into with each other, for
the more successful accomplishment of their crimes, and the more peaceable division of
their spoils.
Thus substantially all the legislation of the world has had its origin
in the desires of one class---of persons to plunder and enslave others, and hold them as
property.
Section III.
In process of time, the robber, or slaveholding, class---who had seized
all the lands, and held all the means of creating wealth---began to discover that the
easiest mode of managing their slaves, and making them profitable, was not for each
slaveholder to hold his specified number of slaves, as he had done before, and as he would
hold so many cattle, but to give them so much liberty as would throw upon themselves (the
slaves) the responsibility of their own subsistence, and yet compel them to sell their
labor to the land-hodling class---their former owners---for just what the latter might
choose to give them.
Of course, these liberated slaves, as some have erroneously called them,
having no lands, or other property, and no means of obtaining an independent subsistence,
had no alternative---to save themselves from starvation---but to sell their labor to the
landholders, in exchange only for the coarsest necessaries of life; not always for so much
even as that.
These liberated slaves, as they were called, were now scarcely less
slaves than they were before. Their means of subsistence were perhaps even more precarious
than when each had his own owner, who had an interest to preserve his life. They were
liable, at the caprice or interest of the landholders, to be thrown out of home,
employment, and the opportunity of even earning a subsistence by their labor. They were,
therefore, in large numbers, driven to the necessity of begging, stealing, or starving;
and became, of course, dangerous to the property and quiet of their late masters.
The consequence was, that these late owners found it necessary, for
their own safety and the safety of their property, to organize themselves more perfectly
as a government and make laws for keeping these dangerous people in subjection; that is,
laws fixing the prices at which they should be compelled to labor, and also prescribing
fearful punishments, even death itself, for such thefts and tresspasses as they were
driven to commit, as their only means of saving themselves from starvation.
These laws have continued in force for hundreds, and, in some countries,
for thousands of years; and are in force to-day, in greater or less severity, in nearly
all the countries on the globe.
The purpose and effect of these laws have been to maintain, in the hands
of the robber, or slave holding class, a monopoly of all lands, and, as far as possible,
of all other means of creating wealth; and thus to keep the great body of laborers in such
a state of poverty and dependence, as would compel them to sell their labor to their
tyrants for the lowest prices at which life could be sustained.
The result of all this is, that the little wealth there is in the world
is all in the hands of a few---that is, in the hands of the law-making, slave-holding
class; who are now as much slaveholders in spirit as they ever were, but who accomplish
their purposes by means of the laws they make for keeping the laborers in subjection and
dependence, instead of each one's owning his individual slaves as so many chattels.
Thus the whole business of legislation, which has now grown to such
gigantic proportions, had its origin in the conspiracies, which have always existed among
the few, for the purpose of holding the many in subjection, and extorting from them their
labor, and all the profits of their labor.
And the real motives and spirit which lie at the foundation of all
legislation---notwithstanding all the pretences and disguises by which they attempt to
hide themselves---are the same to-day as they always have been. They whole purpose of this
legislation is simply to keep one class of men in subordination and servitude to another.
Section IV.
What, then, is legislation? It is an assumption by one man, or body of
men, of absolute, irresponsible dominion over all other men whom they call subject to
their power. It is the assumption by one man, or body of men, of a right to subject all
other men to their will and their service. It is the assumption by one man, or body of
men, of a right to abolish outright all the natural rights, all the natural liberty of all
other men; to make all other men their slaves; to arbitrarily dictate to all other men
what they may, and may not, do; what they may, and may not, have; what they may, and may
not, be. It is, in short, the assumption of a right to banish the principle of human
rights, the principle of justice itself, from off the earth, and set up their own personal
will, pleasure, and interest in its place. All this, and nothing less, is involved in the
very idea that there can be any such thing as human legislation that is obligatory upon
those upon whom it is imposed.
.
NO TREASON:
THE CONSTITUTION OF NO AUTHORITY
[1870]
Chapter 1
The Constitution has no inherent authority or obligation. It has no
authority or obligation at all, unless as a contract between man and man. And it does not
so much as even purport to be a contract between persons now existing. It purports, at
most, to be only a contract between persons living eighty years ago. And it can be
supposed to have been a contract then only between persons who had already come to years
of discretion, so as to be competent to make reasonable and obligatory contracts.
Furthermore, we know, historically, that only a small portion even of the people then
existing were consulted on the subject, or asked, or permitted to express either their
consent or dissent in any formal manner. Those persons, if any, who did give their consent
formally, are all dead now. Most of them have been dead forty, fifty, sixty, or seventy
years. And the constitution, so far as it was their contract, died with them. They had no
natural power or right to make it obligatory upon their children. It is not only plainly
impossible, in the nature of things, that they could bind their posterity, but they did
not even attempt to bind them. That is to say, the instrument does not purport to be an
agreement between any body but "the people" then existing; nor does it, either
expressly or impliedly, assert any right, power, or disposition, on their part, to bind
anybody but themselves. Let us see. Its language is:
We, the people of the United States (that is, the people then existing
in the United States), in order to form a more perfect union, insure domestic tranquility,
provide for the common defense, promote the general welfare, and secure the blessings of
liberty to ourselves and our posterity, do ordain and establish this Constitution for the
United States of America.
It is plain, in the first place, that this language,
as an agreement, purports to be only what it at most really was, viz., a contract between
the people then existing; and, of necessity, binding, as a contract, only upon those then
existing. In the second place, the language neither expresses nor implies that they had
any right or power, to bind their "posterity" to live under it. It does not say
that their "posterity" will, shall, or must live under it. It only says, in
effect, that their hopes and motives in adopting it were that it might prove useful to
their posterity, as well as to themselves, by promoting their union, safety, tranquility,
liberty, etc.
Suppose an agreement were entered into, in this form:
We, the people of Boston, agree to maintain a fort on
Governor's Island, to protect ourselves and our posterity against invasion.
This agreement, as an agreement, would clearly bind
nobody but the people then existing. Secondly, it would assert no right, power, or
disposition, on their part, to compel their "posterity" to maintain such a fort.
It would only indicate that the supposed welfare of their posterity was one of the motives
that induced the original parties to enter into the agreement.
When a man says he is building a house for himself
and his posterity, he does not mean to be understood as saying that he has any thought of
binding them, nor is it to be inferred that he is so foolish as to imagine that he has any
right or power to bind them, to live in it. So far as they are concerned, he only means to
be understood as saying that his hopes and motives, in building it, are that they, or at
least some of them, may find it for their happiness to live in it.
So when a man says he is planting a tree for himself
and his posterity, he does not mean to be understood as saying that he has any thought of
compelling them, nor is it to be inferred that he is such a simpleton as to imagine that
he has any right or power to compel them, to eat the fruit. So far as they are concerned,
he only means to say that his hopes and motives, in planting the tree, are that its fruit
may be agreeable to them.
So it was with those who originally adopted the
Constitution. Whatever may have been their personal intentions, the legal meaning of their
language, so far as their "posterity" was concerned, simply was, that their
hopes and motives, in entering into the agreement, were that it might prove useful and
acceptable to their posterity; that it might promote their union, safety, tranquility, and
welfare; and that it might tend "to secure to them the blessings of liberty."
The language does not assert nor at all imply, any right, power, or disposition, on the
part of the original parties to the agreement, to compel their "posterity" to
live under it. If they had intended to bind their posterity to live under it, they should
have said that their objective was, not "to secure to them the blessings of
liberty," but to make slaves of them; for if their "posterity" are bound to
live under it, they are nothing less than the slaves of their foolish, tyrannical, and
dead grandfathers.
It cannot be said that the Constitution formed
"the people of the United States," for all time, into a corporation. It does not
speak of "the people" as a corporation, but as individuals. A corporation does
not describe itself as "we," nor as "people," nor as
"ourselves." Nor does a corporation, in legal language, have any
"posterity." It supposes itself to have, and speaks of itself as having,
perpetual existence, as a single individuality.
Moreover, no body of men, existing at any one time,
have the power to create a perpetual corporation. A corporation can become practically
perpetual only by the voluntary accession of new members, as the old ones die off. But for
this voluntary accession of new members, the corporation necessarily dies with the death
of those who originally composed it.
Legally speaking, therefore, there is, in the
Constitution, nothing that professes or attempts to bind the "posterity" of
those who established it.
If, then, those who established the Constitution, had
no power to bind, and did not attempt to bind, their posterity, the question arises,
whether their posterity have bound themselves. If they have done so, they can have done so
in only one or both of these two ways, viz., by voting, and paying taxes.
Chapter 2
Let us consider these two matters, voting and tax paying,
separately. And first of voting.
All the voting that has ever taken place under the Constitution, has
been of such a kind that it not only did not pledge the whole people to support the
Constitution, but it did not even pledge any one of them to do so, as the following
considerations show.
1. In the very nature of things, the act of voting could bind nobody
but the actual voters. But owing to the property qualifications required, it is probable
that, during the first twenty or thirty years under the Constitution, not more than
one-tenth, fifteenth, or perhaps twentieth of the whole population (black and white, men,
women, and minors) were permitted to vote. Consequently, so far as voting was concerned,
not more than one-tenth, fifteenth, or twentieth of those then existing, could have
incurred any obligation to support the Constitution.
At the present time, it is probable that not more than one-sixth of the whole
population are permitted to vote. Consequently, so far as voting is concerned, the other
five-sixths can have given no pledge that they will support the Constitution.
2. Of the one-sixth that are permitted to vote, probably not more
than two-thirds (about one-ninth of the whole population) have usually voted. Many never
vote at all. Many vote only once in two, three, five, or ten years, in periods of great
excitement.
No one, by voting, can be said to pledge himself for any longer
period than that for which he votes. If, for example, I vote for an officer who is to hold
his office for only a year, I cannot be said to have thereby pledged myself to support the
government beyond that term. Therefore, on the ground of actual voting, it probably cannot
be said that more than one-ninth or one-eighth, of the whole population are usually under
any pledge to support the Constitution.
3. It cannot be said that, by voting, a man pledges himself to
support the Constitution, unless the act of voting be a perfectly voluntary one on his
part. Yet the act of voting cannot properly be called a voluntary one on the part of any
very large number of those who do vote. It is rather a measure of necessity imposed upon
them by others, than one of their own choice. On this point I repeat what was said in a
former number, viz.:
"In truth, in the case of individuals, their
actual voting is not to be taken as proof of consent, even for the time being. On the
contrary, it is to be considered that, without his consent having even been asked a man
finds himself environed by a government that he cannot resist; a government that forces
him to pay money, render service, and forego the exercise of many of his natural rights,
under peril of weighty punishments. He sees, too, that other men practice this tyranny
over him by the use of the ballot. He sees further, that, if he will but use the ballot
himself, he has some chance of relieving himself from this tyranny of others, by
subjecting them to his own. In short, he finds himself, without his consent, so situated
that, if he use the ballot, he may become a master; if he does not use it, he must become
a slave. And he has no other alternative than these two. In self-defence, he attempts the
former. His case is analogous to that of a man who has been forced into battle, where he
must either kill others, or be killed himself. Because, to save his own life in battle, a
man takes the lives of his opponents, it is not to be inferred that the battle is one of
his own choosing. Neither in contests with the ballot -- which is a mere substitute for a
bullet -- because, as his only chance of self-preservation, a man uses a ballot, is it to
be inferred that the contest is one into which he voluntarily entered; that he voluntarily
set up all his own natural rights, as a stake against those of others, to be lost or won
by the mere power of numbers. On the contrary, it is to be considered that, in an exigency
into which he had been forced by others, and in which no other means of self-defence
offered, he, as a matter of necessity, used the only one that was left to him.
"Doubtless the most miserable of men, under the
most oppressive government in the world, if allowed the ballot, would use it, if they
could see any chance of thereby meliorating their condition. But it would not, therefore,
be a legitimate inference that the government itself, that crushes them, was one which
they had voluntarily set up, or even consented to.
"Therefore, a man's voting under the
Constitution of the United States, is not to be taken as evidence that he ever freely
assented to the Constitution, even for the time being. Consequently we have no proof that
any very large portion, even of the actual voters of the United States, ever really and
voluntarily consented to the Constitution, even for the time being. Nor can we ever have
such proof, until every man is left perfectly free to consent, or not, without thereby
subjecting himself or his property to be disturbed or injured by others."
As we can have no legal knowledge as to who votes
from choice, and who from the necessity thus forced upon him, we can have no legal
knowledge, as to any particular individual, that he voted from choice; or, consequently,
that by voting, he consented, or pledged himself, to support the government. Legally
speaking, therefore, the act of voting utterly fails to pledge any one to support the
government. It utterly fails to prove that the government rests upon the voluntary support
of anybody. On general principles of law and reason, it cannot be said that the government
has any voluntary supporters at all, until it can be distinctly shown who its voluntary
supporters are.
4. As taxation is made compulsory on all, whether
they vote or not, a large proportion of those who vote, no doubt do so to prevent their
own money being used against themselves; when, in fact, they would have gladly abstained
from voting, if they could thereby have saved themselves from taxation alone, to say
nothing of being saved from all the other usurpations and tyrannies of the government. To
take a man's property without his consent, and then to infer his consent because he
attempts, by voting, to prevent that property from being used to his injury, is a very
insufficient proof of his consent to support the Constitution. It is, in fact, no proof at
all. And as we can have no legal knowledge as to who the particular individuals are, if
there are any, who are willing to be taxed for the sake of voting, we can have no legal
knowledge that any particular individual consents to be taxed for the sake of voting; or,
consequently, consents to support the Constitution.
5. At nearly all elections, votes are given for
various candidates for the same office. Those who vote for the unsuccessful candidates
cannot properly be said to have voted to sustain the Constitution. They may, with more
reason, be supposed to have voted, not to support the Constitution, but specially to
prevent the tyranny which they anticipate the successful candidate intends to practice
upon them under color of the Constitution; and therefore may reasonably be supposed to
have voted against the Constitution itself. This supposition is the more reasonable,
inasmuch as such voting is the only mode allowed to them of expressing their dissent to
the Constitution.
6. Many votes are usually given for candidates who have no prospect of
success. Those who give such votes may reasonably be supposed to have voted as they did,
with a special intention, not to support, but to obstruct the exection of, the
Constitution; and, therefore, against the Constitution itself.
7. As all the different votes are given secretly (by
secret ballot), there is no legal means of knowing, from the votes themselves, who votes
for, and who votes against, the Constitution. Therefore, voting affords no legal evidence
that any particular individual supports the Constitution. And where there can be no legal
evidence that any particular individual supports the Constitution, it cannot legally be
said that anybody supports it. It is clearly impossible to have any legal proof of the
intentions of large numbers of men, where there can be no legal proof of the intentions of
any particular one of them.
8. There being no legal proof of any man's
intentions, in voting, we can only conjecture them. As a conjecture, it is probable, that
a very large proportion of those who vote, do so on this principle, viz., that if, by
voting, they could but get the government into their own hands (or that of their friends),
and use its powers against their opponents, they would then willingly support the
Constitution; but if their opponents are to have the power, and use it against them, then
they would NOT willingly support the Constitution.
In short, men's voluntary support of the Constitution
is doubtless, in most cases, wholly contingent upon the question whether, by means of the
Constitution, they can make themselves masters, or are to be made slaves.
Such contingent consent as that is, in law and
reason, no consent at all.
9. As everybody who supports the Constitution by
voting (if there are any such) does so secretly (by secret ballot), and in a way to avoid
all personal responsibility for the acts of his agents or representatives, it cannot
legally or reasonably be said that anybody at all supports the Constitution by voting. No
man can reasonably or legally be said to do such a thing as assent to, or support, the
Constitution, unless he does it openly, and in a way to make himself personally
responsible for the acts of his agents, so long as they act within the limits of the power
he delegates to them.
10. As all voting is secret (by secret ballot), and
as all secret governments are necessarily only secret bands of robbers, tyrants, and
murderers, the general fact that our government is practically carried on by means of such
voting, only proves that there is among us a secret band of robbers, tyrants, and
murderers, whose purpose is to rob, enslave, and, so far as necessary to accomplish their
purposes, murder, the rest of the people. The simple fact of the existence of such a vand
does nothing towards proving that "the people of the United States," or any one
of them, voluntarily supports the Constitution.
For all the reasons that have now been given, voting
furnishes no legal evidence as to who the particular individuals are (if there are any),
who voluntarily support the Constitution. It therefore furnishes no legal evidence that
anybody supports it voluntarily.
So far, therefore, as voting is concerned, the
Constitution, legally speaking, has no supporters at all.
And, as a matter of fact, there is not the slightest
probability that the Constitution has a single bona fide supporter in the country. That is
to say, there is not the slightest probability that there is a single man in the country,
who both understands what the Constitution really is, and sincerely supports it for what
it really is.
The ostensible supporters of the Constitution, like
the ostensible supporters of most other governments, are made up of three classes, viz.:
1. Knaves, a numerous and active class, who see in the government an instrument which they
can use for their own aggrandizement or wealth. 2. Dupes -- a large class, no doubt --
each of whom, because he is allowed one voice out of millions in deciding what he may do
with his own person and his own property, and because he is permitted to have the same
voice in robbing, enslaving, and murdering others, that others have in robbing, enslaving,
and murdering himself, is stupid enough to imagine that he is a "free man," a
"sovereign"; that this is "a free government"; "a government of
equal rights," "the best government on earth," and such like absurdities.
Suppose it be "the best government on earth," does that prove its own goodness,
or only the badness of all other governments? 3. A class who have some appreciation of the
evils of government, but either do not see how to get rid of them, or do not choose to so
far sacrifice their private interests as to give themselves seriously and earnestly to the
work of making a change.
Chapter 3
The payment of taxes, being compulsory, of course furnishes no
evidence that any one voluntarily supports the Constitution.
1. It is true that the theory of our Constitution is, that all taxes
are paid voluntarily; that our government is a mutual insurance company, voluntarily
entered into by the people with each other; that that each man makes a free and purely
voluntary contract with all others who are parties to the Constitution, to pay so much
money for so much protection, the same as he does with any other insurance company; and
that he is just as free not to be protected, and not to pay tax, as he is to pay a tax,
and be protected.
But this theory of our government is wholly different from the
practical fact. The fact is that the government, like a highwayman, says to a man:
"Your money, or your life." And many, if not most, taxes are paid under the
compulsion of that threat.
The government does not, indeed, waylay a man in a lonely place,
spring upon him from the roadside, and, holding a pistol to his head, proceed to rifle his
pockets. But the robbery is none the less a robbery on that account; and it is far more
dastardly and shameful.
The highwayman takes solely upon himself the responsibility, danger,
and crime of his own act. He does not pretend that he has any rightful claim to your
money, or that he intends to use it for your own benefit. He does not pretend to be
anything but a robber. He has not acquired impudence enough to profess to be merely a
"protector," and that he takes men's money against their will, merely to enable
him to "protect" those infatuated travellers, who feel perfectly able to protect
themselves, or do not appreciate his peculiar system of protection. He is too sensible a
man to make such professions as these. Furthermore, having taken your money, he leaves
you, as you wish him to do. He does not persist in following you on the road, against your
will; assuming to be your rightful "sovereign," on account of the
"protection" he affords you. He does not keep "protecting" you, by
commanding you to bow down and serve him; by requiring you to do this, and forbidding you
to do that; by robbing you of more money as often as he finds it for his interest or
pleasure to do so; and by branding you as a rebel, a traitor, and an enemy to your
country, and shooting you down without mercy, if you dispute his authority, or resist his
demands. He is too much of a gentleman to be guilty of such impostures, and insults, and
villanies as these. In short, he does not, in addition to robbing you, attempt to make you
either his dupe or his slave.
The proceedings of those robbers and murderers, who call themselves
"the government," are directly the opposite of these of the single highwayman.
In the first place, they do not, like him, make themselves
individually known; or, consequently, take upon themselves personally the responsibility
of their acts. On the contrary, they secretly (by secret ballot) designate some one of
their number to commit the robbery in their behalf, while they keep themselves practically
concealed. They say to the person thus designated:
Go to A_____ B_____, and say to him that "the government"
has need of money to meet the expenses of protecting him and his property. If he presumes
to say that he has never contracted with us to protect him, and that he wants none of our
protection, say to him that that is our business, and not his; that we choose to protect
him, whether he desires us to do so or not; and that we demand pay, too, for protecting
him. If he dares to inquire who the individuals are, who have thus taken upon themselves
the title of "the government," and who assume to protect him, and demand payment
of him, without his having ever made any contract with them, say to him that that, too, is
our business, and not his; that we do not choose to make ourselves individually known to
him; that we have secretly (by secret ballot) appointed you our agent to give him notice
of our demands, and, if he complies with them, to give him, in our name, a receipt that
will protect him against any similar demand for the present year. If he refuses to comply,
seize and sell enough of his property to pay not only our demands, but all your own
expenses and trouble beside. If he resists the seizure of his property, call upon the
bystanders to help you (doubtless some of them will prove to be members of our band.) If,
in defending his property, he should kill any of our band who are assisting you, capture
him at all hazards; charge him (in one of our courts) with murder; convict him, and hang
him. If he should call upon his neighbors, or any others who, like him, may be disposed to
resist our demands, and they should come in large numbers to his assistance, cry out that
they are all rebels and traitors; that "our country" is in danger; call upon the
commander of our hired murderers; tell him to quell the rebellion and "save the
country," cost what it may. Tell him to kill all who resist, though they should be
hundreds of thousands; and thus strike terror into all others similarly disposed. See that
the work of murder is thoroughly done; that we may have no further trouble of this kind
hereafter. When these traitors shall have thus been taught our strength and our
determination, they will be good loyal citizens for many years, and pay their taxes
without a why or a wherefore.
It is under such compulsion as this that taxes, so called, are paid.
And how much proof the payment of taxes affords, that the people consent to "support
the government," it needs no further argument to show.
2. Still another reason why the payment of taxes implies no consent,
or pledge, to support the government, is that the taxpayer does not know, and has no means
of knowing, who the particular individuals are who compose "the government." To
him "the government" is a myth, an abstraction, an incorporeality, with which he
can make no contract, and to which he can give no consent, and make no pledge. He knows it
only through its pretended agents. "The government" itself he never sees. He
knows indeed, by common report, that certain persons, of a certain age, are permitted to
vote; and thus to make themselves parts of, or (if they choose) opponents of, the
government, for the time being. But who of them do thus vote, and especially how each one
votes (whether so as to aid or oppose the government), he does not know; the voting being
all done secretly (by secret ballot). Who, therefore, practically compose "the
government," for the time being, he has no means of knowing. Of course he can make no
contract with them, give them no consent, and make them no pledge. Of necessity,
therefore, his paying taxes to them implies, on his part, no contract, consent, or pledge
to support them -- that is, to support "the government," or the Constitution.
3. Not knowing who the particular individuals are,
who call themselves "the government," the taxpayer does not know whom he pays
his taxes to. All he knows is that a man comes to him, representing himself to be the
agent of "the government" -- that is, the agent of a secret band of robbers and
murderers, who have taken to themselves the title of "the government," and have
determined to kill everybody who refuses to give them whatever money they demand. or save
his life, he gives up his money to this agent. But as this agent does not make his
principals individually known to the taxpayer, the latter, after he has given up his
money, knows no more who are "the government" -- that is, who were the robbers
-- than he did before. To say, therefore, that by giving up his money to their agent, he
entered into a voluntary contract with them, that he pledges himself to obey them, to
support them, and to give them whatever money they should demand of him in the future, is
simply ridiculous.
4. All political power, so called, rests practically
upon this matter of money. Any number of scoundrels, having money enough to start with,
can establish themselves as a "government"; because, with money, they can hire
soldiers, and with soldiers extort more money; and also compel general obedience to their
will. It is with government, as Caesar said it was in war, that money and soldiers
mutually supported each other; that with money he could hire soldiers, and with soldiers
extort money. So these villains, who call themselves governments, well understand that
their power rests primarily upon money. With money they can hire soldiers, and with
soldiers extort money. And, when their authority is denied, the first use they always make
of money, is to hire soldiers to kill or subdue all who refuse them more money.
For this reason, whoever desires liberty, should
understand these vital facts, viz.: 1. That every man who puts money into the hands of a
"government" (so called), puts into its hands a sword which will be used against
him, to extort more money from him, and also to keep him in subjection to its arbitrary
will. 2. That those who will take his money, without his consent, in the first place, will
use it for his further robbery and enslavement, if he presumes to resist their demands in
the future. 3. That it is a perfect absurdity to suppose that any body of men would ever
take a man's money without his consent, for any such object as they profess to take it
for, viz., that of protecting him; for why should they wish to protect him, if he does not
wish them to do so? To suppose that they would do so, is just as absurd as it would be to
suppose that they would take his moeny without his consent, for the purpose of buying food
or clothing for him, when he did not want it. 4. If a man wants "protection," he
is competent to make his own bargains for it; and nobody has any occasion to rob him, in
order to "protect" him against his will. 5. That the only security men can have
for their political liberty, consists in their keeping their money in their own pockets,
until they have assurances, perfectly satisfactory to themselves, that it will be used as
they wish it to be used, for their benefit, and not for their injury. 6. That no
government, so called, can reasonably be trusted for a moment, or reasonably be supposed
to have honest purposes in view, any longer than it depends wholly upon voluntary support.
These facts are all so vital and so self-evident,
that it cannot reasonably be supposed that any one will voluntarily pay money to a
"government," for the purpose of securing its protection, unless he first make
an explicit and purely voluntary contract with it for that purpose.
It is perfectly evident, therefore, that neither such
voting, nor such payment of taxes, as actually takes place, proves anybody's consent, or
obligation, to support the Constitution. Consequently we have no evidence at all that the
Constitution is binding upon anybody, or that anybody is under any contract or obligation
whatever to support it. And nobody is under any obligation to support it.
Chapter 4
The constitution not only binds nobody now, but it never did bind anybody.
It never bound anybody, because it was never agreed to
by anybody in such a manner as to make it, on general principles of law and reason,
binding upon him.
It is a general principle of law and reason, that a
written instrument binds no one until he has signed it. This principle is so inflexible a
one, that even though a man is unable to write his name, he must still "make his
mark," before he is bound by a written contract. This custom was established ages
ago, when few men could write their names; when a clerk -- that is, a man who could write
-- was so rare and valuable a person, that even if he were guilty of high crimes, he was
entitled to pardon, on the ground that the public could not afford to lose his services.
Even at that time, a written contract must be signed; and men who could not write, either
"made their mark," or signed their contracts by stamping their seals upon wax
affixed to the parchment on which their contracts were written. Hence the custom of
affixing seals, that has continued to this time.
The laws holds, and reason declares, that if a
written instrument is not signed, the presumption must be that the party to be bound by
it, did not choose to sign it, or to bind himself by it. And law and reason both give him
until the last moment, in which to decide whether he will sign it, or not. Neither law nor
reason requires or expects a man to agree to an instrument, until it is written; for until
it is written, he cannot know its precise legal meaning. And when it is written, and he
has had the opportunity to satisfy himself of its precise legal meaning, he is then
expected to decide, and not before, whether he will agree to it or not. And if he do not
then sign it, his reason is supposed to be, that he does not choose to enter into such a
contract. The fact that the instrument was written for him to sign, or with the hope that
he would sign it, goes for nothing. Where would be the end of fraud and litigation, if one
party could bring into court a written instrument, without any signature, and claim to
have it enforced, upon the ground that it was written for another man to sign? that this
other man had promised to sign it? that he ought to have signed it? that he had had the
opportunity to sign it, if he would? but that he had refused or neglected to do so? Yet
that is the most that could ever be said of the Constitution. [Note: The very men who
drafted it, never signed it in any way to bind themselves by it, as a contract. And not
one of them probably ever would have signed it in any way to bind himself by it, as a
contract.] The very judges, who profess to derive all their authority from the
Constitution -- from an instrument that nobody ever signed -- would spurn any other
instrument, not signed, that should be brought before them for adjudication.
Moreover, a written instrument must, in
law and reason, not only be signed, but must also be delivered to the party (or to some
one for him), in whose favor it is made, before it can bind the party making it. The
signing is of no effect, unless the instrument be also delivered. And a party is at
perfect liberty to refuse to deliver a written instrument, after he has signed it. The
Constitution was not only never signed by anybody, but it was never delivered by anybody,
or to anybody's agent or attorney. It can therefore be of no more validity as a contract,
then can any other instrument that was never signed or delivered.
Chapter 5
As further evidence of the general sense of mankind, as to the
practical necessity there is that all men's important contracts, especially those of a
permanent nature, should be both written and signed, the following facts are pertinent.
For nearly two hundred years -- that is, since 1677 -- there has been on the statute book
of England, and the same, in substance, if not precisely in letter, has been re-enacted,
and is now in force, in nearly or quite all the States of this Union, a statute, the
general object of which is to declare that no action shall be brought to enforce contracts
of the more important class, unless they are put in writing, and signed by the parties to
be held chargeable upon them.
The principle of the statute, be it observed, is, not merely that
written contracts shall be signed, but also that all contracts, except for those specially
exempted -- generally those that are for small amounts, and are to remain in force for but
a short time - shall be both written and signed.
The reason of the statute, on this point, is, that it is now so easy
a thing for men to put their contracts in writing, and sign them, and their failure to do
so opens the door to so much doubt, fraud, and litigation, that men who neglect to have
their contracts -- of any considerable importance -- written and signed, ought not to have
the benefit of courts of justice to enforce them. And this reason is a wise one; and that
experience has confirmed its wisdom and necessity, is demonstrated by the fact that it has
been acted upon in England for nearly two hundred years, and has been so nearly
universally adopted in this country, and that nobody thinks of repealing it.
We all know, too, how careful most men are to have their contracts
written and signed, even when this statute does not require it. For example, most men, if
they have money due them, of no larger amount than five or ten dollars, are careful to
take a note for it. If they buy even a small bill of goods, paying for it at the time of
delivery, they take a receipted bill for it. If they pay a small balance of a book
account, or any other small debt previously contracted, they take a written receipt for
it.
Furthermore, the law everywhere (probably) in our country, as well
as in England, requires that a large class of contracts, such as wills, deeds, etc., shall
not only be written and signed, but also sealed, witnessed, and acknowledged. And in the
case of married women conveying their rights in real estate, the law, in many States,
requires that the women shall be examined separate and apart from their husbands, and
declare that they sign their contracts free of any fear or compulsion of their husbands.
Such are some of the precautions which the laws
require, and which individuals -- from motives of common prudence, even in cases not
required by law -- take, to put their contracts in writing, and have them signed, and, to
guard against all uncertainties and controversies in regard to their meaning and validity.
And yet we have what purports, or professes, or is claimed, to be a contract -- the
Constitution -- made eighty years ago, by men who are now all dead, and who never had any
power to bind US, but which (it is claimed) has nevertheless bound three generations of
men, consisting of many millions, and which (it is claimed) will be binding upon all the
millions that are to come; but which nobody ever signed, sealed, delivered, witnessed, or
acknowledged; and which few persons, compared with the whole number that are claimed to be
bound by it, have ever read, or even seen, or ever will read, or see. And of those who
ever have read it, or ever will read it, scarcely any two, perhaps no two, have ever
agreed, or ever will agree, as to what it means.
Moreover, this supposed contract, which would not be
received in any court of justice sitting under its authority, if offered to prove a debt
of five dollars, owing by one man to another, is one by which - as it is generally
interpreted by those who pretend to administer it -- all men, women and children
throughout the country, and through all time, surrender not only all their property, but
also their liberties, and even lives, into the hands of men who by this supposed contract,
are expressly made wholly irresponsible for their disposal of them. And we are so insane,
or so wicked, as to destroy property and lives without limit, in fighting to compel men to
fulfill a supposed contract, which, inasmuch as it has never been signed by anybody, is,
on general princples of law and reason -- such principles as we are all governed by in
regard to other contracts -- the merest waste of paper, binding upon nobody, fit only to
be thrown into the fire; or, if preserved, preserved only to serve as a witness and a
warning of the folly and wickedness of mankind.
Chapter 6
It is no exaggeration, but a literal truth, to say that, by the
Constitution - not as I interpret it, but as it is interpreted by those who pretend to
administer it -- the properties, liberties, and lives of the entire people of the United
States are surrendered unreservedly into the hands of men who, it is provided by the
Constitution itself, shall never be "questioned" as to any disposal they make of
them.
Thus the Constitution (Art. I, Sec. 6) provides that, "for any
speech or debate (or vote), in either house, they (the senators and representatives) shall
not be questioned in any other place."
The whole law-making power is given to these senators and
representatives (when acting by a two-thirds vote [Note: And this two-thirds vote may be
but two-thirds of a quorum -- that is two-thirds of a majority -- instead of two-thirds of
the whole.]); and this provision protects them from all responsibility for the laws they
make.
The Constitution also enables them to secure the
execution of all their laws, by giving them power to withhold the salaries of, and to
impeach and remove, all judicial and executive officers, who refuse to execute them.
Thus the whole power of the government is in their hands, and they
are made utterly irresponsible for the use they make of it. What is this but absolute,
irresponsible power?
It is no answer to this view of the case to say that
these men are under oath to use their power only within certain limits; for what care
they, or what should they care, for oaths or limits, when it is expressly provided, by the
Constitution itself, that they shall never be "questioned," or held to any
resonsibility whatever, for violating their oaths, or transgressing those limits? Neither
is it any answer to this view of the case to say that the men holding this absolute,
irresponsible power, must be men chosen by the people (or portions of them) to hold it. A
man is none the less a slave because he is allowed to choose a new master once in a term
of years. Neither are a people any the less slaves because permitted periodically to
choose new masters. What makes them slaves is the fact that they now are, and are always
hereafter to be, in the hands of men whose power over them is, and always is to be,
absolute and irresponsible. Of what appreciable value is it to any man, as an individual,
that he is allowed a voice in choosing these public masters? His voice is only one of
several millions.
The right of absolute and irresponsible dominion is
the right of property, and the right of property is the right of absolute, irresponsible
dominion. The two are identical; the one necessarily implies the other. Neither can exist
without the other. If, therefore, Congress have that absolute and irresponsible law-making
power, which the Constitution -- according to their interpretation of it -- gives them, it
can only be because they own us as property. If they own us as property, they are our
masters, and their will is our law. If they do not own us as property, they are not our
masters, and their will, as such, is of no authority over us.
But these men who claim and exercise this absolute
and irresponsible dominion over us, dare not be consistent, and claim either to be our
masters, or to own us as property. They say they are only our servants, agents, attorneys,
and representatives. But this declaration involves an absurdity, a contradiction. No man
can be my servant, agent, attorney, or representative, and be, at the same time,
uncontrollable by me, and irresponsible to me for his acts. It is of no importance that I
appointed him, and put all power in his hands. If I made him uncontrollable by me, and
irresponsible to me, he is no longer my servant, agent, attorney, or representative. If I
gave him absolute, irresponsible power over my property, I gave him the property. If I
gave him absolute, irresponsible power over myself, I made him my master, and gave myself
to him as a slave. And it is of no importance whether I called him master or servant,
agent or owner. The only question is, what power did I put in his hands? Was it an
absolute and irresponsible one? or a limited and responsible one?
For still another reason they are neither our
servants, agents, attorneys, nor representatives. And that reason is, that we do not make
ourselves responsible for their acts. If a man is my servant, agent, or attorney, I
necessarily make myself responsible for all his acts done within the limits of the power I
have intrusted to him. If I have intrusted him, as my agent, with either absolute power,
or any power at all, over the persons or properties of other men than myself, I thereby
necessarily make myself responsible to those other persons for any injuries he may do
them, so long as he acts within the limits of the power I have granted him. But no
individual who may be injured in his person or property, by acts of Congress, can come to
the individual electors, and hold them responsible for these acts of their so-called
agents or representatives. This fact proves that these pretended agents of the people, of
everybody, are really the agents of nobody.
If, then, nobody is individually responsible for the
acts of Congress, the members of Congress are nobody's agents. And if they are nobody's
agents, they are themselves individually responsible for their own acts, and for the acts
of all whom they employ. And the authority they are exercising is simply their own
individual authority; and, by the law of nature -- the highest of all laws -- anybody
injured by their acts, anybody who is deprived by them of his property or his liberty, has
the same right to hold them individually responsible, that he has to hold any other
trespasser individually responsible. He has the same right to resist them, and their
agents, that he has to resist any other trespassers.
Chapter 7
It is plain, then, that on general principles of law and reason --
such principles as we all act upon in courts of justice and in common life -- the
Constitution is no contract; that it binds nobody, and never did bind anybody; and that
all those who pretend to act by its authority, are really acting without any legitimate
authority at all; that, on general principles of law and reason, they are mere usurpers,
and that everybody not only has the right, but is morally bound, to treat them as such.
If the people of this country wish to maintain such a
government as the Constitution describes, there is no reason in the world why they should
not sign the instrument itself, and thus make known their wishes in an open, authentic
manner; in such manner as the common sense and experience of mankind have shown to be
reasonable and necessary in such cases; and in such a manner as to make themselves (as
they ought to do) individually responsible for the acts of the government. But the people
have never been asked to sign it. And the only reason why they have never been asked to
sign it, has been that it has been known that they never would sign it; that they were
neither such fools nor knaves as they must needs have been to be willing to sign it; that
(at least as it has been practically interpreted) it is not what any sensible and honest
man wants for himself; nor such as he has any right to impose upon others. It is, to all
moral intents and purposes, as destitute of obligations as the compacts which robbers and
thieves and pirates enter into with each other, but never sign.
If any considerable number of the people believe the
Constitution to be good, why do they not sign it themselves, and make laws for, and
administer them upon, each other; leaving all other persons (who do not interfere with
them) in peace? Until they have tried the experiment for themselves, how can they have the
face to impose the Constitution upon, or even to recommend it to, others? Plainly the
reason for absurd and inconsistent conduct is that they want the Constitution, not solely
for any honest or legitimate use it can be of to themselves or others, but for the
dishonest and illegitimate power it gives them over the persons and properties of others.
But for this latter reason, all their eulogiums on the Constitution, all their
exhortations, and all their expenditures of money and blood to sustain it, would be
wanting.
Chapter 8
The Constitution itself, then, being of no authority, on what
authority does our government practically rest? On what ground can those who pretend to
administer it, claim the right to seize men's property, to restrain them of their natural
liberty of action, industry, and trade, and to kill all who deny their authority to
dispose of men's properties, liberties, and lives at their pleasure or discretion?
The most they can say, in answer to this question, is, that some
half, two-thirds, or three-fourths, of the male adults of the country have a tacit
understanding that they will maintain a government under the Constitution; that they will
select, by ballot, the persons to administer it; and that those persons who may receive a
majority, or a plurality, of their ballots, shall act as their representatives, and
administer the Constitution in their name, and by their authority.
But this tacit understanding (admitting it to exist) cannot at all
justify the conclusion drawn from it. A tacit understanding between A, B, and C, that they
will, by ballot, depute D as their agent, to deprive me of my property, liberty, or life,
cannot at all authorize D to do so. He is none the less a robber, tyrant, and murderer,
because he claims to act as their agent, than he would be if he avowedly acted on his own
responsibility alone.
Neither am I bound to recognize him as their agent, nor can he
legitimately claim to be their agent, when he brings no written authority from them
accrediting him as such. I am under no obligation to take his word as to who his
principals may be, or whether he has any. Bringing no credentials, I have a right to say
he has no such authority even as he claims to have: and that he is therefore intending to
rob, enslave, or murder me on his own account.
This tacit understanding, therefore, among the voters of the
country, amounts to nothing as an authority to their agents. Neither do the ballots by
which they select their agents, avail any more than does their tacit understanding; for
their ballots are given in secret, and therefore in such a way as to avoid any personal
responsibility for the acts of their agents.
No body of men can be said to authorize a man to act as their agent, to
the injury of a third person, unless they do it in so open and authentic a manner as to
make themselves personally responsible for his acts. None of the voters in this country
appoint their political agents in any open, authentic manner, or in any manner to make
themselves responsible for their acts. Therefore these pretended agents cannot
legitimately claim to be really agents. Somebody must be responsible for the acts of these
pretended agents; and if they cannot show any open and authentic credentials from their
principals, they cannot, in law or reason, be said to have any principals. The maxim
applies here, that what does not appear, does not exist. If they can show no principals,
they have none.
But even these pretended agents do not themselves know who their
pretended principals are. These latter act in secret; for acting by secret ballot is
acting in secret as much as if they were to meet in secret conclave in the darkness of the
night. And they are personally as much unknown to the agents they select, as they are to
others. No pretended agent therefore can ever know by whose ballots he is selected, or
consequently who his real principles are. Not knowing who his principles are, he has no
right to say that he has any. He can, at most, say only that he is the agent of a secret
band of robbers and murderers, who are bound by that faith which prevails among
confederates in crime, to stand by him, if his acts, done in their name, shall be
resisted.
Men honestly engaged in attempting to establish
justice in the world, have no occasion thus to act in secret; or to appoint agents to do
acts for which they (the principals) are not willing to be responsible.
The secret ballot makes a secret government; and a
secret government is a secret band of robbers and murderers. Open despotism is better than
this. The single despot stands out in the face of all men, and says: I am the State: My
will is law: I am your master: I take the responsibility of my acts: The only arbiter I
acknowledge is the sword: If anyone denies my right, let him try conclusions with me.
But a secret government is little less than a
government of assassins. Under it, a man knows not who his tyrants are, until they have
struck, and perhaps not then. He may guess, beforehand, as to some of his immediate
neighbors. But he really knows nothing. The man to whom he would most naturally fly for
protection, may prove an enemy, when the time of trial comes.
This is the kind of government we have; and it is the
only one we are likely to have, until men are ready to say: We will consent to no
Constitution, except such an one as we are neither ashamed nor afraid to sign; and we will
authorize no government to do anything in our name which we are not willing to be
personally responsible for.
Chapter 9
What is the motive to the secret ballot? This, and only this: Like
other confederates in crime, those who use it are not friends, but enemies; and they are
afraid to be known, and to have their individual doings known, even to each other. They
can contrive to bring about a sufficient understanding to enable them to act in concert
against other persons; but beyond this they have no confidence, and no friendship, among
themselves. In fact, they are engaged quite as much in schemes for plundering each other,
as in plundering those who are not of them. And it is perfectly well understood among them
that the strongest party among them will, in certain contingencies, murder each other by
the hundreds of thousands (as they lately did do) to accomplish their purposes against
each other. Hence they dare not be known, and have their individual doings known, even to
each other. And this is avowedly the only reason for the ballot: for a secret government;
a government by secret bands of robbers and murderers. And we are insane enough to call
this liberty! To be a member of this secret band of robbers and murderers is esteemed a
privilege and an honor! Without this privilege, a man is considered a slave; but with it a
free man! With it he is considered a free man, because he has the same power to secretly
(by secret ballot) procure the robbery, enslavement, and murder of another man, and that
other man has to procure his robbery, enslavement, and murder. And this they call equal
rights!
If any number of men, many or few, claim the right to govern the
people of this country, let them make and sign an open compact with each other to do so.
Let them thus make themselves individually known to those whom they propose to govern. And
let them thus openly take the legitimate responsibility of their acts. How many of those
who now support the Constitution, will ever do this? How many will ever dare openly
proclaim their right to govern? or take the legitimate responsibility of their acts? Not
one!
Chapter 10
It is obvious that, on general principles of law and reason, there
exists no such thing as a government created by, or resting upon, any consent, compact, or
agreement of "the people of the United States" with each other; that the only
visible, tangible, responsible government that exists, is that of a few individuals only,
who act in concert, and call themselves by the several names of senators, representatives,
presidents, judges, marshals, treasurers, collectors, generals, colonels, captains, etc.,
etc.
On general principles of law and reason, it is of no importance
whatever that these few individuals profess to be the agents and representatives of
"the people of the United States"; since they can show no credentials from the
people themselves; they were never appointed as agents or representatives in any open,
authentic manner; they do not themselves know, and have no means of knowing, and cannot
prove, who their principals (as they call them) are individually; and consequently cannot,
in law or reason, be said to have any principals at all.
It is obvious, too, that if these alleged principals ever did
appoint these pretended agents, or representatives, they appointed them secretly (by
secret ballot), and in a way to avoid all personal responsibility for their acts; that, at
most, these alleged principals put these pretended agents forward for the most criminal
purposes, viz.: to plunder the people of their property, and restrain them of their
liberty; and that the only authority that these alleged principals have for so doing, is
simply a tacit understanding among themselves that they will imprison, shoot, or hang
every man who resists the exactions and restraints which their agents or representatives
may impose upon them.
Thus it is obvious that the only visible, tangible government we
have is made up of these professed agents or representatives of a secret band of robbers
and murderers, who, to cover up, or gloss over, their robberies and murders, have taken to
themselves the title of "the people of the United States"; and who, on the
pretense of being "the people of the United States," assert their right to
subject to their dominion, and to control and dispose of at their pleasure, all property
and persons found in the United States.
Chapter 11
On general principles of law and reason, the oaths which these
pretended agents of the people take "to support the Constitution," are of no
validity or obligation. And why? For this, if for no other reason, viz., that they are
given to nobody. There is no privity (as the lawyers say) -- that is, no mutual
recognition, consent, and agreement -- between those who take these oaths, and any other
persons.
If I go upon Boston Common, and in the presence of a hundred
thousand people, men, women and children, with whom I have no contract upon the subject,
take an oath that I will enforce upon them the laws of Moses, of Lycurgus, of Solon, of
Justinian, or of Alfred, that oath is, on general principles of law and reason, of no
obligation. It is of no obligation, not merely because it is intrinsically a criminal one,
but also because it is given to nobody, and consequently pledges my faith to nobody. It is
merely given to the winds.
It would not alter the case at all to say that, among these hundred
thousand persons, in whose presence the oath was taken, there were two, three, or five
thousand male adults, who had secretly -- by secret ballot, and in a way to avoid making
themselves individually known to me, or to the remainder of the hundred thousand --
designated me as their agent to rule, control, plunder, and, if need be, murder, these
hundred thousand people. The fact that they had designated me secretly, and in a manner to
prevent my knowing them individually, prevents all privity between them and me; and
consequently makes it impossible that there can be any contract, or pledge of faith, on my
part towards them; for it is impossible that I can pledge my faith, in any legal sense, to
a man whom I neither know, nor have any means of knowing, individually.
So far as I am concerned, then, these two, three, or five thousand
persons are a secret band of robbers and murderers, who have secretly, and in a way to
save themselves from all responsibility for my acts, designated me as their agent; and
have, through some other agent, or pretended agent, made their wishes known to me. But
being, nevertheless, individually unknown to me, and having no open, authentic contract
with me, my oath is, on general principles of law and reason, of no validity as a pledge
of faith to them. And being no pledge of faith to them, it is no pledge of faith to
anybody. It is mere idle wind. At most, it is only a pledge of faith to an unknown band of
robbers and murderers, whose instrument for plundering and murdering other people, I thus
publicly confess myself to be. And it has no other obligation than a similar oath given to
any other unknown body of pirates, robbers, and murderers.
For these reasons the oaths taken by members of Congress, "to
support the Constitution," are, on general principles of law and reason, of no
validity. They are not only criminal in themselves, and therefore void; but they are also
void for the further reason that they are given to nobody.
It cannot be said that, in any legitimate or legal
sense, they are given to "the people of the United States"; because neither the
whole, nor any large proportion of the whole, people of the United States ever, either
openly or secretly, appointed or designated these men as their agents to carry the
Constitution into effect. The great body of the people -- that is, men, women, and
children -- were never asked, or even permitted, to signify, in any formal manner, either
openly or secretly, their choice or wish on the subject. The most that these members of
Congress can say, in favor of their appointment, is simply this: Each one can say for
himself:
I have evidence satisfactory to myself, that there
exists, scattered throughout the country, a band of men, having a tacit understanding with
each other, and calling themselves "the people of the United States," whose
general purposes are to control and plunder each other, and all other persons in the
country, and, so far as they can, even in neighboring countries; and to kill every man who
shall attempt to defend his person and property against their schemes of plunder and
dominion. Who these men are, individually, I have no certain means of knowing, for they
sign no papers, and give no open, authentic evidence of their individual membership. They
are not known individually even to each other. They are apparently as much afraid of being
individually known to each other, as of being known to other persons. Hence they
ordinarily have no mode either of exercising, or of making known, their individual
membership, otherwise than by giving their votes secretly for certain agents to do their
will. \ But although these men are individually unknown, both to each other and to other
persons, it is generally understood in the country that none but male persons, of the age
of twenty-one years and upwards, can be members. It is also generally understood that all
male persons, born in the country, having certain complexions, and (in some localities)
certain amounts of property, and (in certain cases) even persons of foreign birth, are
permitted to be members. But it appears that usually not more than one half, two-thirds,
or in some cases, three-fourths, of all who are thus permitted to become members of the
band, ever exercise, or consequently prove, their actual membership, in the only mode in
which they ordinarily can exercise or prove it, viz., by giving their votes secretly for
the officers or agents of the band. The number of these secret votes, so far as we have
any account of them, varies greatly from year to year, thus tending to prove that the
band, instead of being a permanent organization, is a merely pro tempore affair with those
who choose to act with it for the time being. \ The gross number of these secret votes, or
what purports to be their gross number, in different localities, is occasionally
published. Whether these reports are accurate or not, we have no means of knowing. It is
generally supposed that great frauds are often committed in depositing them. They are
understood to be received and counted by certain men, who are themselves appointed for
that purpose by the same secret process by which all other officers and agents of the band
are selected. According to the reports of these receivers of votes (for whose accuracy or
honesty, however, I cannot vouch), and according to my best knowledge of the whole number
of male persons "in my district," who (it is supposed) were permitted to vote,
it would appear that one-half, two-thirds or three-fourths actually did vote. Who the men
were, individually, who cast these votes, I have no knowledge, for the whole thing was
done secretly. But of the secret votes thus given for what they call a "member of
Congress," the receivers reported that I had a majority, or at least a larger number
than any other one person. And it is only by virtue of such a designation that I am now
here to act in concert with other persons similarly selected in other parts of the
country. It is understood among those who sent me here, that all persons so selected,
will, on coming together at the City of Washington, take an oath in each other's presence
"to support the Constitution of the United States." By this is meant a certain
paper that was drawn up eighty years ago. It was never signed by anybody, and apparently
has no obligation, and never had any obligation, as a contract. In fact, few persons ever
read it, and doubtless much the largest number of those who voted for me and the others,
never even saw it, or now pretend to know what it means. Nevertheless, it is often spoken
of in the country as "the Constitution of the United States"; and for some
reason or other, the men who sent me here, seem to expect that I, and all with whom I act,
will swear to carry this Constitution into effect. I am therefore ready to take this oath,
and to co-operate with all others, similarly selected, who are ready to take the same
oath.
This is the most that any member of Congress can say
in proof that he has any constituency; that he represents anybody; that his oath "to
support the Constitution," is given to anybody, or pledges his faith to anybody. He
has no open, written, or other authentic evidence, such as is required in all other cases,
that he was ever appointed the agent or representative of anybody. He has no written power
of attorney from any single individual. He has no such legal knowledge as is required in
all other cases, by which he can identify a single one of those who pretend to have
appointed him to represent them.
Of course his oath, professedly given to them, "to
support the Constitution," is, on general principles of law and reason, an oath given
to nobody. It pledges his faith to nobody. If he fails to fulfil his oath, not a single
person can come forward, and say to him, you have betrayed me, or broken faith with me.
No one can come forward and say to him: I appointed
you my attorney to act for me. I required you to swear that, as my attorney, you would
support the Constitution. You promised me that you would do so; and now you have forfeited
the oath you gave to me. No single individual can say this.
No open, avowed, or responsible association, or body
of men, can come forward and say to him: We appointed you our attorney, to act forus. We
required you to swear that, as our attorney, you would support the Constitution. You
promised us that you would do so; and now you have forfeited the oath you gave to us.
No open, avowed, or responsible association, or body
of men, can say this to him; because there is no such association or body of men in
existence. If any one should assert that there is such an association, let him prove, if
he can, who compose it. Let him produce, if he can, any open, written, or other authentic
contract, signed or agreed to by these men; forming themselves into an association; making
themselves known as such to the world; appointing him as their agent; and making
themselves individually, or as an association, responsible for his acts, done by their
authority. Until all this can be shown, no one can say that, in any legitimate sense,
there is any such association; or that he is their agent; or that he ever gave his oath to
them; or ever pledged his faith to them.
On general principles of law and reason, it would be
a sufficient answer for him to say, to all individuals, and to all pretended associations
of individuals, who should accuse him of a breach of faith to them:
I never knew you. Where is your evidence that you,
either individually or collectively, ever appointed me your attorney? that you ever
required me to swear to you, that, as your attorney, I would support the Constitution? or
that I have now broken any faith that I ever pledged to you? You may, or you may not, be
members of that secret band of robbers and murderers, who act in secret; appoint their
agents by a secret ballot; who keep themselves individually unknown even to the agents
they thus appoint; and who, therefore, cannot claim that they have any agents; or that any
of their pretended agents ever gave his oath, or pledged his faith to them. I repudiate
you altogether. My oath was given to others, with whom you have nothing to do; or it was
idle wind, given only to the idle winds. Begone!
Chapter 12
For the same reasons, the oaths of all the other pretended agents of
this secret band of robbers and murderers are, on general principles of law and reason,
equally destitute of obligation. They are given to nobody; but only to the winds.
The oaths of the tax-gatherers and treasurers of the
band, are, on general principles of law and reason, of no validity. If any tax gatherer,
for example, should put the money he receives into his own pocket, and refuse to part with
it, the members of this band could not say to him: You collected that money as our agent,
and for our uses; and you swore to pay it over to us, or to those we should appoint to
receive it. You have betrayed us, and broken faith with us.
It would be a sufficient answer for him to say to
them:
I never knew you. You never made yourselves
individually known to me. I never game by oath to you, as individuals. You may, or you may
not, be members of that secret band, who appoint agents to rob and murder other people;
but who are cautious not to make themselves individually known, either to such agents, or
to those whom their agents are commissioned to rob. If you are members of that band, you
have given me no proof that you ever commissioned me to rob others for your benefit. I
never knew you, as individuals, and of course never promised you that I would pay over to
you the proceeds of my robberies. I committed my robberies on my own account, and for my
own profit. If you thought I was fool enough to allow you to keep yourselves concealed,
and use me as your tool for robbing other persons; or that I would take all the personal
risk of the robberies, and pay over the proceeds to you, you were particularly simple. As
I took all the risk of my robberies, I propose to take all the profits. Begone! You are
fools, as well as villains. If I gave my oath to anybody, I gave it to other persons than
you. But I really gave it to nobody. I only gave it to the winds. It answered my purposes
at the time. It enabled me to get the money I was after, and now I propose to keep it. If
you expected me to pay it over to you, you relied only upon that honor that is said to
prevail among thieves. You now understand that that is a very poor reliance. I trust you
may become wise enough to never rely upon it again. If I have any duty in the matter, it
is to give back the money to those from whom I took it; not to pay it over to villains
such as you.
Chapter 13
On general principles of law and reason, the oaths which foreigners take,
on coming here, and being "naturalized" (as it is called), are of no validity.
They are necessarily given to nobody; because there is no open, authentic association, to
which they can join themselves; or to whom, as individuals, they can pledge their faith.
No such association, or organization, as "the people of the United States,"
having ever been formed by any open, written, authentic, or voluntary contract, there is,
on general principles of law and reason, no such association, or organization, in
existence. And all oaths that purport to be given to such an association are necessarily
given only to the winds. They cannot be said to be given to any man, or body of men, as
individuals, because no man, or body of men, can come forward with any proof that the
oaths were given to them, as individuals, or to any association of which they are members.
To say that there is a tacit understanding among a portion of the male adults of the
country, that they will call themselves "the people of the United States," and
that they will act in concert in subjecting the remainder of the people of the United
States to their dominion; but that they will keep themselves personally concealed by doing
all their acts secretly, is wholly insufficient, on general principles of law and reason,
to prove the existence of any such association, or organization, as "the people of
the United States"; or consequently to prove that the oaths of foreigners were given
to any such association.
Chapter 14
On general principles of law and reason, all the oaths which, since
the war, have been given by Southern men, that they will obey the laws of Congress,
support the Union, and the like, are of no validity. Such oaths are invalid, not only
because they were extorted by military power, and threats of confiscation, and because
they are in contravention of men's natural right to do as they please about supporting the
government, but also because they were given to nobody. They were nominally given to
"the United States." But being nominally given to "the United States,"
they were necessarily given to nobody, because, on general principles of law and reason,
there were no "United States," to whom the oaths could be given. That is to say,
there was no open, authentic, avowed, legitimate association, corporation, or body of men,
known as "the United States," or as "the people of the United States,"
to whom the oaths could have been given. If anybody says there was such a corporation, let
him state who were the individuals that composed it, and how and when they became a
corporation. Were Mr. A, Mr. B, and Mr. C members of it? If so, where are their
signatures? Where the evidence of their membership? Where the record? Where the open,
authentic proof? There is none. Therefore, in law and reason, there was no such
corporation.
On general principles of law and reason, every corporation,
association, or organized body of men, having a legitimate corporate existence, and
legitimate corporate rights, must consist of certain known individuals, who can prove, by
legitimate and reasonable evidence, their membership. But nothing of this kind can be
proved in regard to the corporation, or body of men, who call themselves "the United
States." Not a man of them, in all the Northern States, can prove by any legitimate
evidence, such as is required to prove membership in other legal corporations, that he
himself, or any other man whom he can name, is a member of any corporation or association
called "the United States," or "the people of the United States," or,
consequently, that there is any such corporation. And since no such corporation can be
proved to exist, it cannot of course be proved that the oaths of Southern men were given
to any such corporation. The most that can be claimed is that the oaths were given to a
secret band of robbers and murderers, who called themselves "the United States,"
and extorted those oaths. But that is certainly not enough to prove that the oaths are of
any obligation.
Chapter 15
On general principles of law and reason, the oaths of soldiers, that
they will serve a given number of years, that they will obey the the orders of their
superior officers, that they will bear true allegiance to the government, and so forth,
are of no obligation. Independently of the criminality of an oath, that, for a given
number of years, he will kill all whom he may be commanded to kill, without exercising his
own judgment or conscience as to the justice or necessity of such killing, there is this
further reason why a soldier's oath is of no obligation, viz., that, like all the other
oaths that have now been mentioned, it is given to nobody. There being, in no legitimate
sense, any such corporation, or nation, as "the United States," nor,
consequently, in any legitimate sense, any such government as "the government of the
United States," a soldier's oath given to, or contract made with, such a nation or
government, is necessarily an oath given to, or contract made with, nobody. Consequently
such an oath or contract can be of no obligation.
Chapter 16
On general principles of law and reason, the treaties, so called,
which purport to be entered into with other nations, by persons calling themselves
ambassadors, secretaries, presidents, and senators of the United States, in the name, and
in behalf, of "the people of the United States," are of no validity. These
so-called ambassadors, secretaries, presidents, and senators, who claim to be the agents
of "the people of the United States" for making these treaties, can show no
open, written, or other authentic evidence that either the whole "people of the
United States," or any other open, avowed, responsible body of men, calling
themselves by that name, ever authorized these pretended ambassadors and others to make
treaties in the name of, or binding upon any one of, "the people of the United
States," or any other open, avowed, responsible body of men, calling themselves by
that name, ever authorized these pretended ambassadors, secretaries, and others, in their
name and behalf, to recognize certain other persons, calling themselves emperors, kings,
queens, and the like, as the rightful rulers, sovereigns, masters, or representatives of
the different peoples whom they assume to govern, to represent, and to bind.
The "nations," as they are called, with whom our pretended
ambassadors, secretaries, presidents, and senators profess to make treaties, are as much
myths as our own. On general principles of law and reason, there are no such
"nations." That is to say, neither the whole people of England, for example, nor
any open, avowed, responsible body of men, calling themselves by that name, ever, by any
open, written, or other authentic contract with each other, formed themselves into any
bona fide, legitimate association or organization, or authorized any king, queen, or other
representative to make treaties in their name, or to bind them, either individually, or as
an association, by such treaties.
Our pretended treaties, then, being made with no legitimate or bona
fide nations, or representatives of nations, and being made, on our part, by persons who
have no legitimate authority to act for us, have instrinsically no more validity than a
pretended treaty made by the Man in the Moon with the king of the Pleiades.
Chapter 17
On general principles of law and reason, debts contracted in the
name of "the United States," or of "the people of the United States,"
are of no validity. It is utterly absurd to pretend that debts to the amount of
twenty-five hundred millions of dollars are binding upon thirty-five or forty millions of
people, when there is not a particle of legitimate evidence -- such as would be required
to prove a private debt -- that can be produced against any one of them, that either he,
or his properly authorized attorney, ever contracted to pay one cent.
Certainly, neither the whole people of the United States, nor any
number of them, ever separately or individually contracted to pay a cent of these debts.
Certainly, also, neither the whole people of the United States, nor
any number of them, every, by any open, written, or other authentic and voluntary
contract, united themselves as a firm, corporation, or association, by the name of
"the United States," or "the people of the United States," and
authorized their agents to contract debts in their name.
Certainly, too, there is in existence no such firm, corporation, or
association as "the United States," or "the people of the United
States," formed by any open, written, or other authentic and voluntary contract, and
having corporate property with which to pay these debts.
How, then, is it possible, on any general principle of law or
reason, that debts that are binding upon nobody individually, can be binding upon forty
millions of people collectively, when, on general and legitimate principles of law and
reason, these forty millions of people neither have, nor ever had, any corporate property?
never made any corporate or individual contract? and neither have, nor ever had, any
corporate existence?
Who, then, created these debts, in the name of "the United
States"? Why, at most, only a few persons, calling themselves "members of
Congress," etc., who pretended to represent "the people of the United
States," but who really represented only a secret band of robbers and murderers, who
wanted money to carry on the robberies and murders in which they were then engaged; and
who intended to extort from the future people of the United States, by robbery and threats
of murder (and real murder, if that should prove necessary), the means to pay these debts.
This band of robbers and murderers, who were the real principals in
contracting these debts, is a secret one, because its members have never entered into any
open, written, avowed, or authentic contract, by which they may be individually known to
the world, or even to each other. Their real or pretended representatives, who contracted
these debts in their name, were selected (if selected at all) for that purpose secretly
(by secret ballot), and in a way to furnish evidence against none of the principals
individually; and these principals were really known individually neither to their
pretended representatives who contracted these debts in their behalf, nor to those who
lent the money. The money, therefore, was all borrowed and lent in the dark; that is, by
men who did not see each other's faces, or know each other's names; who could not then,
and cannot now, identify each other as principals in the transactions; and who
consequently can prove no contract with each other.
Furthermore, the money was all lent and borrowed for criminal
purposes; that is, for purposes of robbery and murder; and for this reason the contracts
were all intrinsically void; and would have been so, even though the real parties,
borrowers and lenders, had come face to face, and made their contracts openly, in their
own proper names.
Furthermore, this secret band of robbers and murderers, who were the
real borrowers of this money, having no legitimate corporate existence, have no corporate
property with which to pay these debts. They do indeed pretend to own large tracts of wild
lands, lying between the Atlantic and Pacific Oceans, and between the Gulf of Mexico and
the North Pole. But, on general principles of law and reason, they might as well pretend
to own the Atlantic and Pacific Oceans themselves; or the atmosphere and the sunlight; and
to hold them, and dispose of them, for the payment of these debts.
Having no corporate property with which to pay what purports to be
their corporate debts, this secret band of robbers and murderers are really bankrupt. They
have nothing to pay with. In fact, they do not propose to pay their debts otherwise than
from the proceeds of their future robberies and murders. These are confessedly their sole
reliance; and were known to be such by the lenders of the money, at the time the money was
lent. And it was, therefore, virtually a part of the contract, that the money should be
repaid only from the proceeds of these future robberies and murders. For this reason, if
for no other, the contracts were void from the beginning.
In fact, these apparently two classes, borrowers and lenders, were
really one and the same class. They borrowed and lent money from and to themselves. They
themselves were not only part and parcel, but the very life and soul, of this secret band
of robbers and murderers, who borrowed and spent the money. Individually they furnished
money for a common enterprise; taking, in return, what purported to be corporate promises
for individual loans. The only excuse they had for taking these so-called corporate
promises of, for individual loans by, the same parties, was that they might have some
apparent excuse for the future robberies of the band (that is, to pay the debts of
the corporation), and that they might also know what shares they were to be
respectively entitled to out of the proceeds of their future robberies.
Finally, if these debts had been created for the most innocent and
honest purposes, and in the most open and honest manner, by the real parties to the
contracts, these parties could thereby have bound nobody but themselves, and no property
but their own. They could have bound nobody that should have come after them, and no
property subsequently created by, or belonging to, other persons.
Chapter 18
The Constitution having never been signed by anybody; and there being
no other open, written, or authentic contract between any parties whatever, by virtue of
which the United States government, so called, is maintained; and it being well known that
none but male persons, of twenty-one years of age and upwards, are allowed any voice in
the government; and it being also well known that a large number of these adult persons
seldom or never vote at all; and that all those who do vote, do so secretly (by secret
ballot), and in a way to prevent their individual votes being known, either to the world,
or even to each other; and consequently in a way to make no one openly responsible for the
acts of their agents, or representatives, -- all these things being known, the questions
arise: who compose the real governing power in the country? Who are the men, the
responsible men, who rob us of our property? Restrain us of our liberty? Subject us to
their arbitrary dominion? And devastate our hooms, and shoot us down by the hundreds of
thousands, if we resist? How shall we find these men? How shall we know them from others?
How shall we defend ourselves and our property against them? Who, of our neighbors, are
members of this secret band of robbers and murderers? How can we know which are their
houses, that we may burn or demolish them? Which their property, that we may destroy it?
Which their persons, that we may kill them, and rid the world and ourselves of such
tyrants and monsters?
These are questions that must be answered, before men can be free;
before they can protect themselves against this secret band of robbers and murderers, who
now plunder, enslave, and destroy them.
The answer to these questions is, that only those who have the will
and power to shoot down their fellow men, are the real rulers in this, as in all other
(so-called) civilized countries; for by no others will civilized men be robbed, or
enslaved.
Among savages, mere physical strength, on the part of
one man, may enable him to rob, enslave, or kill another man. Among barbarians, mere
physical strength, on the part of a body of men, disciplined, and acting in concert,
though with very little money or other wealth, may, under some circumstances, enable them
to rob, enslave, or kill another body of men, as numerous, or perhaps even more numerous,
than themselves. And among both savages and barbarians, mere want may sometimes compel one
man to sell himself as a slave to another. But with (so-called) civilized peoples, among
whom knowledge, wealth, and the means of acting in concert, have becom diffusede; and who
have invented such weapons and other means of defense as to render mere physical strength
of less importance; and by whom soldiers in any requisite number, and other
instrumentalities of war in any requisite amount, can always be had for money, the
question of war, and consequently the question of power, is little else than a mere
question of money. As a necessary consequence, those who stand ready to furnish this
money, are the real rulers. It is so in Europe, and it is so in this country.
In Europe, the nominal rulers, the emperors and kings
and parliaments, are anything but the real rulers of their respective countries. They are
little or nothing else than mere tools, employed by the wealthy to rob, enslave, and (if
need be) murder those who have less wealth, or none at all.
The Rosthchilds, and that class of money-lenders of
whom they are the representatives and agents -- men who never think of lending a shilling
to their next-door neighbors, for purposes of honest industry, unless upon the most ample
security, and at the highest rate of interest -- stand ready, at all times, to lend money
in unlimited amounts to those robbers and murderers, who call themselves governments, to
be expended in shooting down those who do not submit quietly to being robbed and enslaved.
They lend their money in this manner, knowing that it
is to be expended in murdering their fellow men, for simply seeking their liberty and
their rights; knowing also that neither the interest nor the principal will ever be paid,
except as it will be extorted under terror of the repetition of such murders as those for
which the money lent is to be expended.
These money-lenders, the Rosthchilds, for example,
say to themselves: If we lend a hundred millions sterling to the queen and parliament of
England, it will enable them to murder twenty, fifty, or a hundred thousand people in
England, Ireland, or India; and the terror inspired by such wholesale slaughter, will
enable them to keep the whole people of those countries in subjection for twenty, or
perhaps fifty, years to come; to control all their trade and industry; and to extort from
them large amounts of money, under the name of taxes; and from the wealth thus extorted
from them, they (the queen and parliament) can afford to pay us a higher rate of interest
for our money than we can get in any other way. Or, if we lend this sum to the emperor of
Austria, it will enable him to murder so many of his people as to strike terror into the
rest, and thus enable him to keep them in subjection, and extort money from them, for
twenty or fifty years to come. And they say the same in regard to the emperor of Russia,
the king of Prussia, the emperor of France, or any other ruler, so called, who, in their
judgment, will be able, by murdering a reasonable portion of his people, to keep the rest
in subjection, and extort money from them, for a long time to come, to pay the interest
and the principal of the money lent him.
And why are these men so ready to lend money for
murdering their fellow men? Soley for this reason, viz., that such loans are considered
better investments than loans for purposes of honest industry. They pay higher rates of
interest; and it is less trouble to look after them. This is the whole matter.
The question of making these loans is, with these
lenders, a mere question of pecuniary profit. They lend money to be expended in robbing,
enslaving, and murdering their fellow men, solely because, on the whole, such loans pay
better than any others. They are no respecters of persons, no superstitious fools, that
reverence monarchs. They care no more for a king, or an emperor, than they do for a
beggar, except as he is a better customer, and can pay them better interest for their
money. If they doubt his ability to make his murders successful for maintaining his power,
and thus extorting money from his people in future, they dismiss him unceremoniously as
they would dismiss any other hopeless bankrupt, who should want to borrow money to save
himself from open insolvency.
When these great lenders of blood-money, like the
Rothschilds, have loaned vast sums in this way, for purposes of murder, to an emperor or a
king, they sell out the bonds taken by them, in small amounts, to anybody, and everybody,
who are disposed to buy them at satisfactory prices, to hold as investments. They (the
Rothschilds) thus soon get back their money, with great profits; and are now ready to lend
money in the same way again to any other robber and murderer, called an emperor or king,
who, they think, is likely to be successful in his robberies and murders, and able to pay
a good price for the money necessary to carry them on. This business of lending
blood-money is one of the most thoroughly sordid, cold-blooded, and criminal that was ever
carried on, to any considerable extent, amongst human beings. It is like lending money to
slave traders, or to common robbers and pirates, to be repaid out of their plunder. And
the men who loan money to governments, so called, for the purpose of enabling the latter
to rob, enslave, and murder their people, are among the greatest villains that the world
has ever seen. And they as much deserve to be hunted and killed (if they cannot otherwise
be got rid of) as any slave traders, robbers, or pirates that ever lived.
When these emperors and kings, so-called, have
obtained their loans, they proceed to hire and train immense numbers of professional
murderers, called soldiers, and employ them in shooting down all who resist their demands
for money. In fact, most of them keep large bodies of these murderers constantly in their
service, as their only means of enforcing their extortions. There are now, I think, four
or five millions of these professional murderers constantly employed by the so-called
sovereigns of Europe. The enslaved people are, of course, forced to support and pay all
these murderers, as well as to submit to all the other extortions which these murderers
are employed to enforce.
It is only in this way that most of the so-called
governments of Europe are maintained. These so-called governments are in reality only
great bands of robbers and murderers, organized, disciplined, and constantly on the alert.
And the so-called sovereigns, in these different governments, are simply the heads, or
chiefs, of different bands of robbers and murderers. And these heads or chiefs are
dependent upon the lenders of blood-money for the means to carry on their robberies and
murders. They could not sustain themselves a moment but for the loans made to them by
these blood-money loan-mongers. And their first care is to maintain their credit with
them; for they know their end is come, the instant their credit with them fails.
Consequently the first proceeds of their extortions are scrupulously applied to the
payment of the interest on their loans.
In addition to paying the interest on their bonds,
they perhaps grant to the holders of them great monopolies in banking, like the Banks of
England, of France, and of Vienna; with the agreement that these banks shall furnish money
whenever, in sudden emergencies, it may be necessary to shoot down more of their people.
Perhaps also, by means of tariffs on competing imports, they give great monopolies to
certain branches of industry, in which these lenders of blood-money are engaged. They
also, by unequal taxation, exempt wholly or partially the property of these loan-mongers,
and throw corresponding burdens upon those who are too poor and weak to resist.
Thus it is evident that all these men, who call
themselves by the high-sounding names of Emperors, Kings, Sovereigns, Monarchs, Most
Christian Majesties, Most Catholic Majesties, High Mightinesses, Most Serene and Potent
Princes, and the like, and who claim to rule "by the grace of God," by
"Divine Right" -- that is, by special authority from Heaven -- are intrinsically
not only the merest miscreants and wretches, engaged solely in plundering, enslaving, and
murdering their fellow men, but that they are also the merest hangers on, the servile,
obsequious, fawning dependents and tools of these blood-money loan-mongers, on whom they
rely for the means to carry on their crimes. These loan-mongers, like the Rothschilds,
laugh in their sleeves, and say to themselves: These despicable creatures, who call
themselves emperors, and kings, and majesties, and most serene and potent princes; who
profess to wear crowns, and sit on thrones; who deck themselves with ribbons, and
feathers, and jewels; and surround themselves with hired flatterers and lickspittles; and
whom we suffer to strut around, and palm themselves off, upon fools and slaves, as
sovereigns and lawgivers specially appointed by Almighty God; and to hold themselves out
as the sole fountains of honors, and dignities, and wealth, and power -- all these
miscreants and imposters know that we make them, and use them; that in us they live, move,
and have their being; that we require them (as the price of their positions) to take upon
themselves all the labor, all the danger, and all the odium of all the crimes they commit
for our profit; and that we will unmake them, strip them of their gewgaws, and send them
out into the world as beggars, or give them over to the vengeance of the people they have
enslaved, the moment they refuse to commit any crime we require of them, or to pay over to
us such share of the proceeds of their robberies as we see fit to demand.
Chapter 19
Now, what is true in Europe, is substantially true in
this country. The difference is the immaterial one, that, in this country, there is no
visible, permanent head, or chief, of these robbers and murderers who call themselves
"the government." That is to say, there is no one man, who calls himself the
state, or even emperor, king, or sovereign; no one who claims that he and his children
rule "by the Grace of God," by "Divine Right," or by special
appointment from Heaven. There are only certain men, who call themselves presidents,
senators, and representatives, and claim to be the authorized agents, for the time being
or for certain short periods, of all "the people of the United States"; but who
can show no credentials, or powers of attorney, or any other open, authentic evidence that
they are so; and who notoriously are not so; but are really only the agents of a secret
band of robbers and murderers, whom they themselves do not know, and have no means of
knowing, individually; but who, they trust, will openly or secretly, when the crisis
comes, sustain them in all their usurpations and crimes.
What is important to be noticed is, that these
so-called presidents, senators, and representatives, these pretended agents of all
"the people of the United States," the moment their exactions meet with any
formidable resistance from any portion of "the people" themselves, are obliged,
like their co-robbers and murderers in Europe, to fly at once to the lenders of blood
money, for the means to sustain their power. And they borrow their money on the same
principle, and for the same purpose, viz., to be expended in shooting down all those
"people of the United States" -- their own constituents and principals, as they
profess to call them -- who resist the robberies and enslavements which these borrowers of
the money are practising upon them. And they expect to repay the loans, if at all, only
from the proceeds of the future robberies, which they anticipate it will be easy for them
and their successors to perpetrate through a long series of years, upon their pretended
principals, if they can but shoot down now some hundreds of thousands of them, and thus
strike terror into the rest.
Perhaps the facts were never made more evident, in
any country on the globe, than in our own, that these soulless blood-money loan-mongers
are the real rulers; that they rule from the most sordid and mercenary motives; that the
ostensible government, the presidents, senators, and representatives, so called, are
merely their tools; and that no ideas of, or regard for, justice or liberty had anything
to do in inducing them to lend their money for the [civil] war. In proof of all this, look
at the following facts.
Nearly a hundred years ago we professed to have got
rid of all that religious superstition, inculcated by a servile and corrupt priesthood in
Europe, that rulers, so called, derived their authority directly from Heaven; and that it
was consequently a religious duty on the part of the people to obey them. We professed
long ago to have learned that governments could rightfully exist only by the free will,
and on the voluntary support, of those who might choose to sustain them. We all professed
to have known long ago, that the only legitimate objects of government were the
maintenance of liberty and justice equally for all. All this we had professed for nearly a
hundred years. And we professed to look with pity and contempt upon those ignorant,
superstitious, and enslaved peoples of Europe, who were so easily kept in subjection by
the frauds and force of priests and kings.
Notwithstanding all this, that we had learned, and
known, and professed, for nearly a century, these lenders of blood money had, for a long
series of years previous to the war, been the willing accomplices of the slave-holders in
perverting the government from the purposes of liberty and justice, to the greatest of
crimes. They had been such accomplices for a purely pecuniary consideration, to wit, a
control of the markets in the South; in other words, the privilege of holding the
slave-holders themselves in industrial and commercial subjection to the manufacturers and
merchants of the North (who afterwards furnished the money for the war). And these
Northern merchants and manufacturers, these lenders of blood-money, were willing to
continue to be the accomplices of the slave-holders in the future, for the same pecuniary
considerations. But the slave-holders, either doubting the fidelity of their Northern
allies, or feeling themselves strong enough to keep their slaves in subjection without
Northern assistance, would no longer pay the price which these Northern men demanded. And
it was to enforce this price in the future -- that is, to monopolize the Southern markets,
to maintain their industrial and commercial control over the South -- that these Northern
manufacturers and merchants lent some of the profits of their former monopolies for the
war, in order to secure to themselves the same, or greater, monopolies in the future.
These -- and not any love of liberty or justice -- were the motives on which the money for
the war was lent by the North. In short, the North said to the slave-holders: If you will
not pay us our price (give us control of your markets) for our assistance against your
slaves, we will secure the same price (keep control of your markets) by helping your
slaves against you, and using them as our tools for maintaining dominion over you; for the
control of your markets we will have, whether the tools we use for that purpose be black
or white, and be the cost, in blood and money, what it may.
On this principle, and from this motive, and not from
any love of liberty, or justice, the money was lent in enormous amounts, and at enormous
rates of interest. And it was only by means of these loans that the objects of the war
were accomplished.
And now these lenders of blood-money demand their
pay; and the government, so called, becomes their tool, their servile, slavish, villanous
tool, to extort it from the labor of the enslaved people both of the North and South. It
is to be extorted by every form of direct, and indirect, and unequal taxation. Not only
the nominal debt and interest -- enormous as the latter was -- are to be paid in full; but
these holders of the debt are to be paid still further -- and perhaps doubly, triply, or
quadruply paid -- by such tariffs on imports as will enable our home manufacturers to
realize enormous prices for their commodities; also by such monopolies in banking as will
enable them to keep control of, and thus enslave and plunder, the industry and trade of
the great body of the Northern people themselves. In short, the industrial and commercial
slavery of the great body of the people, North and South, black and white, is the price
which these lenders of blood money demand, and insist upon, and are determined to secure,
in return for the money lent for the war.
This programme having been fully arranged and
systematized, they put their sword into the hands of the chief murderer of the war,
[President Grant, the famous general in the civil war] and charge him to carry their
scheme into effect. And now he, speaking as their organ, says, "Let us have
peace."
The meaning of this is: Submit quietly to all the
robbery and slavery we have arranged for you, and you can have "peace." But in
case you resist, the same lenders of blood-money, who furnished the means to subdue the
South, will furnish the means again to subdue you. These are the terms on which alone this
government, or, with few exceptions, any other, ever gives "peace" to its
people.
The whole affair, on the part of those who furnished
the money, has been, and now is, a deliberate scheme of robbery and murder; not merely to
monopolize the markets of the South, but also to monopolize the currency, and thus control
the industry and trade, and thus plunder and enslave the laborers, of both North and
South. And Congress and the president are today the merest tools for these purposes. They
are obliged to be, for they know that their own power, as rulers, so-called, is at an end,
the moment their credit with the blood-money loan-mongers fails. They are like a bankrupt
in the hands of an extortioner. They dare not say nay to any demand made upon them. And to
hide at once, if possible, both their servility and crimes, they attempt to divert public
attention, by crying out that they have "Abolished Slavery!" That they have
"Saved the Country!" That they have "Preserved our Glorious Union!"
and that, in now paying the "National Debt," as they call it (as if the people
themselves, all of them who are taxed for its payment, had really and voluntarily joined
in contracting it), they are simply "Maintaining the National Honor!"
By "maintaining the national honor," they
mean simply that they themselves, open robbers and murderers, assume to be the nation, and
will keep faith with those who lend them the money necessary to enable them to crush the
great body of the people under their feet; and will faithfully appropriate, from the
proceeds of their future robberies and murders, enough to pay all their loans, principal
and interest.
The pretense that the "abolition of
slavery" was either a motive or justification for the war, is a fraud of the same
character with that of "maintaining the national honor." Who, but such usurpers,
robbers, and murderers as they, ever established slavery? Or what government, except one
resting upon the sword, like the one we now have, was ever capable of maintaining slavery?
And why did these men abolish slavery? Not from any love of liberty in general -- not as
an act of justice to the black man himself, but only "as a war measure," and
because they wanted his assistance, and that of his friends, in carrying on the war they
had undertaken for maintaining and intensifying that political, commercial, and industrial
slavery, to which they have subjected the great body of the people, both black and white.
And yet these imposters now cry out that they have abolished the chattel slavery of the
black man -- although that was not the motive of the war -- as if they thought they could
thereby conceal, atone for, or justify that other slavery which they were fighting to
perpetuate, and to render more rigorous and inexorable than it ever was before. There was
no difference of principle -- but only of degree -- between the slavery they boast they
have abolished, and the slavery they were fighting to preserve; for all restraints upon
men's natural liberty, not necessary for the simple maintenance of justice, are of the
nature of slavery, and differ from each other only in degree.
If their object had really been to abolish slavery,
or maintain liberty or justice generally, they had only to say: All, whether white or
black, who want the protection of this government, shall have it; and all who do not want
it, will be left in peace, so long as they leave us in peace. Had they said this, slavery
would necessarily have been abolished at once; the war would have been saved; and a
thousand times nobler union than we have ever had would have been the result. It would
have been a voluntary union of free men; such a union as will one day exist among all men,
the world over, if the several nations, so called, shall ever get rid of the usurpers,
robbers, and murderers, called governments, that now plunder, enslave, and destroy them.
Still another of the frauds of these men is, that
they are now establishing, and that the war was designed to establish, "a government
of consent." The only idea they have ever manifested as to what is a government of
consent, is this -- that it is one to which everybody must consent, or be shot. This idea
was the dominant one on which the war was carried on; and it is the dominant one, now that
we have got what is called "peace."
Their pretenses that they have "Saved the
Country," and "Preserved our Glorious Union," are frauds like all the rest
of their pretenses. By them they mean simply that they have subjugated, and maintained
their power over, an unwilling people. This they call "Saving the Country"; as
if an enslaved and subjugated people -- or as if any people kept in subjection by the
sword (as it is intended that all of us shall be hereafter) -- could be said to have any
country. This, too, they call "Preserving our Glorious Union"; as if there could
be said to be any Union, glorious or inglorious, that was not voluntary. Or as if there
could be said to be any union between masters and slaves; between those who conquer, and
those who are subjugated.
All these cries of having "abolished
slavery," of having "saved the country," of having "preserved the
union," of establishing "a government of consent," and of "maintaining
the national honor," are all gross, shameless, transparent cheats -- so transparent
that they ought to deceive no one -- when uttered as justifications for the war, or for
the government that has suceeded the war, or for now compelling the people to pay the cost
of the war, or for compelling anybody to support a government that he does not
want. The lesson taught by all these facts is this: As long as mankind
continue to pay "national debts," so-called -- that is, so long as they are such
dupes and cowards as to pay for being cheated, plundered, enslaved, and murdered -- so
long there will be enough to lend the money for those purposes; and with that money a
plenty of tools, called soldiers, can be hired to keep them in subjection. But when they
refuse any longer to pay for being thus cheated, plundered, enslaved, and murdered, they
will cease to have cheats, and usurpers, and robbers, and murderers and blood-money
loan-mongers for masters.
Inasmuch as the Constitution was never signed, nor
agreed to, by anybody, as a contract, and therefore never bound anybody, and is now
binding upon nobody; and is, moreover, such an one as no people can ever hereafter be
expected to consent to, except as they may be forced to do so at the point of the bayonet,
it is perhaps of no importance what its true legal meaning, as a contract, is.
Nevertheless, the writer thinks it proper to say that, in his opinion, the Constitution is
no such instrument as it has generally been assumed to be; but that by false
interpretations, and naked usurpations, the government has been made in practice a very
widely, and almost wholly, different thing from what the Constitution itself purports to
authorize. He has heretofore written much, and could write much more, to prove that such
is the truth. But whether the Constitution really be one thing, or another, this much is
certain -- that it has either authorized such a government as we have had, or has been
powerless to prevent it. In either case, it is unfit to exist.
Lysander Spooner
Home
------------------------------------------------------------------------